Viewing entries in
Opinion

Developing Our Environment: Planting the Seeds for the Activist Model

Despite popular opinion, I think you should be rooted in the topic no matter what your politics, performance, or method of engagement is. Having a conversation about military force, animal rights, or economic sanctions provides unique moments for conversation that leads us to unearth scholarship buried in libraries and catalogues that inspire us each and every year. A lot of arguments on the January/February topic seem to be about avoiding or being able to initiate topicality debates to preserve the value in these conversations. What is seldom done in this search for the perfectly balanced conversation at the Tournament of Champions, unfortunately, is to question what do T debates mean outside of wins and losses? Even if a given topic is great, what does it mean for the individual competitors that might not share your subject position?  What does a conversation mean and who is it for if it’s not accessible for the most disadvantaged students who find the time to compete?

Developing Our Environment: Planting the Seeds for the Activist Model

Despite popular opinion, I think you should be rooted in the topic no matter what your politics, performance, or method of engagement is. Having a conversation about military force, animal rights, or economic sanctions provides unique moments for conversation that leads us to unearth scholarship buried in libraries and catalogues that inspire us each and every year. A lot of arguments on the January/February topic seem to be about avoiding or being able to initiate topicality debates to preserve the value in these conversations. What is seldom done in this search for the perfectly balanced conversation at the Tournament of Champions, unfortunately, is to question what do T debates mean outside of wins and losses? Even if a given topic is great, what does it mean for the individual competitors that might not share your subject position?  What does a conversation mean and who is it for if it’s not accessible for the most disadvantaged students who find the time to compete?

An Open Letter About Subtle Sexism In Debate by Asher Bykov

Graphic by Grace Doyle and Areeba Amer of the Greenhill School.The views and opinions expressed in this article are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of Victory Briefs.Asher Bykov debated for Roslyn High School’s Speech and Debate Team for 4 years, where he held a leadership role for 3 years. Some of his major accomplishments include leading his Lincoln Douglas team to first place in New York State, reaching Lincoln Douglas finals of the New York State Forensic League Competition as a junior, receiving his school’s first TOC bid in Public Forum with his brother, and breaking at various national tournaments. Asher Bykov now runs The Debate Without Debate Podcast with his brother, Joseph Bykov, where they hope to break through their echo chambers by inviting extra-ordinary ordinary guests on to create a forum for deliberation without all the smoke and mirrors you see on the news. He will be attending Georgetown University in the fall.


As we drove home from the train station, I received a call from my elated brother, who won first place at a local tournament and qualified to States. “Yes!”Waiting for my team to arrive at school, I could barely stand still. When the yellow school bus pulled into the circle and my teammates filed off, a large group of us celebrated. We gathered around laughing and high-fiving, congratulating the trophy-holders, but something wasn’t right: the two women who went to the tournament stood to the side, apart from the energetic group of guys that gathered around me.After we got in the car to drive home, my friend poked my side. “Why didn’t you include the girls in your celebration? They are part of your team too you know.”I got defensive. “I have no control over the situation. I’m just closer with the guys anyway.”This interaction has stuck with me for the past year. It sticks because it represents my greatest shortcoming as a member and leader of my Speech and Debate team.There are plenty of articles on the overt sexism that challenges the Speech and Debate community, as well as the workplace at large. However, there seems to be a lack of focus on an equally damaging form of discrimination: subtle sexism.Jessica Bennett, journalist and author of Feminist Fight Club, defines subtle sexism as “things like being interrupted when you speak — something that happens twice as frequently to women as men — or being mistaken for the office secretary when you’re actually the one in charge. It’s the fact that women who lead are perceived as bossy or too aggressive, that when we negotiate for money we’re disliked (and less likely to receive said money), and when we ask for something twice we’re viewed as nags.” She also notes that “while overt sexism is inarguably bad and inexcusable, that doesn’t mean subtle sexism isn’t damaging—oftentimes it’s even more dangerous because it’s harder to document, and even harder to call out.”Although Bennett focuses her conversations on the workplace, I believe the premise also applies to the Speech and Debate community. Subtle sexism in debate includes behaviors like cutting a woman off during a cross examination or an explanation of a decision (typically under the assumption that you are “simply more knowledgeable” or “a better debater” than she is), chastising the “showy-ness” (or lack thereof) of women’s clothing, and making sexual comments during practices. “When a woman walks into the debate space, she’s immediately judged for being too conservative in a dress or too promiscuous in a dress; there’s no gray area for us,” explained Kati Johnson, an accomplished debater from Texas. “When we’re ‘too nice’ outside of rounds or to judges, guys frequently label us as flirty and then talk about us behind our backs, oftentimes with objectifying rhetoric. When we succeed, we get labeled as one of the best girls in debate, not just one of the best debaters.”In the excerpt from the beginning of this article, I was subtly sexist when I unconsciously excluded women on my team by only celebrating with my male teammates. As a leader, I had an obligation to encourage a collective group celebration, not reinforce separate, gender divided ones. I dropped the ball, failed to meet my duty. I also accept responsibility for the fact that I was likely subtly sexist in other incidents, some of which I may still be unaware of.Now I am not here to bash on all men, nor am I here to make the assertion everyone is subtly sexist; however, we need to acknowledge that these problems exist and that they have more ramifications than we might think. Studies have shown that subtle sexism reduces performance, actively makes the environment feel uncomfortable, and, ultimately, drives women out of the workforce. Jessica Bennett equates this phenomenon with “death by a thousand cuts.”In debate, this means, point blank, we are all worse off because of subtle sexism. Our teammates will feel out of place, our friends will be unable to reach their full potential, and we will lose valuable members of our community. Given the individualism encouraged by the competitive nature of some events in Speech and Debate, we can easily forget the importance of the collective aspect of our activity. At its core, Speech and Debate is better because we find our “team.” Whether you are a lone wolf who finds other independent debaters or are fortunate enough to have an established program at your school, when we work together, we can achieve far more than when we allow subtle sexism to fester and divide us.In an ideal universe, debaters would only need to focus on debating. Unfortunately, we don’t live in that world, but there are actionable steps we can take to stop subtle sexism and bring ourselves closer to equality.

So, what steps can we take to progress?

Recognize that subtle sexism is real. We can only solve a problem when we admit that there is a problem. If a member of your team brings up a complaint about a comment you or another member made, address it. We are all fallible, but don’t rush to brush these events aside because they will only build and breed toxicity.Have an open conversation about subtle sexism. This year, I took time to sit down with my teammates to discuss the small things that we did, although sometimes unintentionally, that may have driven some women out of our club. It was also crucial for us to revisit women who left the activity to better understand their perspective. As much as men on the team can isolate what they think pushed women out of the activity, there is nothing more accurate than going directly to those affected. In my own school, these exercises led us to be one of the strongest teams on our local circuit, helped us break onto the national circuit, and has contributed to an increasing number of women in the club and its leadership. Even with our recent success, though, work is still required to ensure greater equality and representation in our club.Men must hold themselves, as well as other men, accountable. Having conversations about subtle sexism and raising awareness of its effects means nothing if men are not willing to take it on themselves to make changes. In my case, this meant making an active effort to include women in our post-competition celebrations. For others, it may mean stopping jokes that make other members feel uncomfortable or calling other men out for their exclusionary behavior. It can be difficult to address these issues, especially when we have a personal connection to the situation. However, our first reaction should not be defensive. We ought to listen to others and become open to change.Understand that it isn’t totally a “you” problem. Too often, I have heard that “men are the source of all of these issues” or “the activity would be much better without men.” While it is important for us to express our thoughts freely, these claims are frankly reductionist and threaten to reinforce subtle sexism. Breaking this system requires us to recognize that we are all responsible for subtle sexism, while also understanding that there are other societal factors at play. Now that we are aware of it, however, we have an obligation to flip the script, even if it involves hard conversations and bumps along the road.On a more concrete level, I must re-emphasize the importance of women in leadership roles. All of the suggestions I mentioned previously materialize faster when women have opportunities to excel and lead an activity. Furthermore, a strong female leader(s) implicitly encourages more women to join the activity and reduces toxic masculinity on the team. She can act as a role model for other women and provide a unique perspective that results in positive change for a team. Ultimately, we cannot hope to address the problems associated with subtle sexism in this community if people are actively excluded from the conversation.


Author’s End Note:This article is the result of a significant amount of time talking to my teammates, receiving constructive criticism, and self-reflection. Thank you to my friends who allowed me to highlight their experience in this piece and to those who helped me refine my message.I recognize that non-binary and trans debaters are influenced by subtle sexism, but, as a cis-white-straight-male, I feel uncomfortable discussing a topic that I have no experience with. I welcome any suggestions from people more familiar with these experiences in debate.Every situation is different and requires unique solutions, but I hope this piece can spark a larger conversation about this topic and its implications in the community.
Links and Resources:Jessica Bennett Interview: https://goop.com/work/career/are-you-subtly-sexist-most-likely-yes/Studies on subtle sexism: https://www.fastcompany.com/3031101/the-new-subtle-sexism-toward-women-in-the-workplaceFrom the Bennett quote: https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/0261927X14533197?papetoc=, http://gap.hks.harvard.edu/how-can-women-escape-compensation-negotiation-dilemma-relational-accounts-are-one-answer, http://www.womendontask.com/stats.html 

VBI Staff Topic Recommendations

Voting for 2019-2020 LD topics ends on August 7th. To help voters fill out their ballots we asked a panel of distinguished  VBI instructors to rank all of the potential topics and provide what their 'ideal slate' of topics from the list would look like.

On Hypocritical Theory by Jake Nebel

The views and opinions expressed in this article are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of Victory Briefs.Jake Nebel is an executive director at Victory Briefs and (starting fall 2019) assistant professor of philosophy at USC. He recently completed his PhD in philosophy at NYU.

1 Introduction

Suppose you’re late to meet your friend for lunch. When you arrive fifteen minutes late, your friend is upset. They say that your tardiness was disrespectful, wrong, and so on. They blame you, and you have no excuse. But here’s the twist: your friend has been late to the past several lunch meetings you’ve had.Is their blame appropriate? This question is distinct from two others: whether you did anything wrong, and whether you are thereby blameworthy. You did wrong by showing up late. And, since you have no excuse, you are blameworthy. But it doesn’t follow that your friend is right to blame you. Arguably, they don’t have the standing or authority to blame, condemn, or criticize you for being late, because they are so often late themselves.This is an example of hypocritical blame. Hypocritical blame is when one person blames another for violating a norm that they (the blamer) themselves have recently violated or are disposed to violate. Intuitively, in such cases, the act of blame is inappropriate even if the person being blamed is blameworthy for acting wrongly.My aim in this article is to highlight a practice in debate that is structurally analogous to hypocritical blame, and to suggest a strategy for dealing with this practice. The practice is what I call hypocritical theory. A hypocritical theory interpretation is one that a debater advocates that they themselves recently violated or will soon violate. A theory interpretation may become hypocritical at either of two times: first, when the debater advocates it (in, say, round 2) after having violated it in some prior round (round 1); or, second, when the debater violates it (in, say, round 2) after having advocated it in some prior round (round 1). I intend the label of “hypocritical theory” to apply to cases of both kinds.Note that, in calling certain arguments or practices “hypocritical,” I don’t mean that they or their proponents are in any way bad or blameworthy or unvirtuous. I don’t mean that their proponents are hypocrites in the ordinary, morally loaded sense that they habitually do things that they believe or assert to be wrong. The definition is merely stipulative; the point of the label is just to highlight the structural analogy to hypocritical blame. Hypocritical theory is relevantly like hypocritical blame in that it involves complaint, criticism, or condemnation of an act that one has engaged in oneself, even if the nature of that complaint is not particularly moral.Although my discussion is explicitly focused on theory interpretations, I suspect it may also apply to other kinds of pre-fiat criticism and advocacy (e.g., certain kritiks). What these positions have in common, for present purposes, is that their links/violations are committed by debaters—things they do or say—and that their alternatives/interpretations have or at least include debaters as their agents. If the affirmative debater is supposed to lose for being complicit with capitalism, for example, and if the “we” who should reject capitalism includes the debaters in the room (which it presumably does if the alternative requires the judge to vote one way or another), then this makes it possible for the advocacy to be hypocritical in the relevant sense—e.g., because its proponent linked in the very same way just last round.I also intend the label of “hypocritical theory” to cover topicality, at least as it’s most commonly run. In most topicality debates, the negative argues that the affirmative should lose for failing to present an advocacy that affirms the resolution. This contains two logically independent parts: a theoretical rule requiring the affirmative to be topical, and an interpretation of what the resolution means. When these two advocacies are combined, they justify a single rule requiring the affirmative to affirm some particular proposition at tournaments using the given resolution. If the debater advancing that rule violates it in other rounds, by defending an advocacy that does not affirm that particular proposition, then the topicality challenge was, in the relevant sense, hypocritical.1What I propose is a norm against hypocritical theory and hypocritical “debate blame” more generally. I believe that the norm should be imposed bottom-up by debaters, via theory argument, not top-down by judges. The content of the norm is this:

The Nonhypocrisy Norm:
Debaters must meet their own interpretations (and other pre-fiat advocacies) for at least the entire tournament in which those interpretations are proposed, and may only advocate interpretations that they have met throughout the tournament.

The penalty for violating the nonhypocrisy norm should be whatever penalty was proposed by the debater who violates it.In stating this norm, I have specified a duration—the tournament—which is somewhat artificial and which may therefore seem arbitrary. Some arbitrariness is inevitable because the notion of hypocritical blame (and therefore hypocritical theory) is, to some extent, vague: it’s vague whether a person engaged in some behavior “recently.” Two hours ago may count as determinately recent, and three years ago may count as determinately not recent, but there is no precise threshold in between. Just because some debater ran multiple necessary-but-insufficient burdens as a freshman shouldn’t mean that they forfeit the right to run theory against those arguments as a senior. One has to choose between maintaining the vagueness of our ordinary concept and introducing an arbitrary threshold. I have chosen the latter, because a debate tournament is a natural unit of competitive preparation and allows for some adjustment in interpretations within a single topic and each debater’s career. But either path seems to me defensible.In the rest of this article, I’ll give some arguments for the nonhypocrisy norm and consider several objections to it. I’ll start with arguments that appeal to the general impropriety of hypocritical blame, and then argue (more compellingly, I think) that adopting the nonhypocrisy norm would be good for debate.

2 Hypocritical Blame

The first kind of argument for the nonhypocrisy norm is that it is supported by the more general (non-debate-specific) reasons against hypocritical blame. The philosophical literature contains several accounts of the problem with hypocritical blame, but I’ll just mention three of them here.According to Scanlon (2008), blame is supposed to mark an impairment in a relationship. But, in cases of hypocritical blame, the blamer has already impaired the relationship, and so lacks the key complaint that supports blame. This may be applied to debate because, even if a proponent of hypocritical theory has not impaired the narrow relationship between themselves and their opponent, they (arguably) impair a wider relationship—i.e., between all competitors in a tournament, or all participants of the activity. Theory interpretations are generally justified by the impairments to fairness and education caused by their violations. Harms to those common goods are impairments to debate as an activity or community even if no particular competitor or member of the community can be identified as harmed.According to Wallace (2010), hypocritical blame is inappropriate because it denies our equal moral standing as persons. The hypocritical blamer treats their own interest in avoiding blame as more important than the corresponding interest of others. Similarly, since debaters have an interest in avoiding the kind of punishment involved in losing a theory argument, the proponent of a hypocritical theory interpretation treats their own interest in avoiding punishment as more important than the corresponding interest of others. This is unfair because all competitors have an equal claim to having that interest respected.According to Fritz and Miller (2018), hypocritical blame is unfair because it manifests an unjustified “differential blaming disposition.” The idea is that we ought to treat people in different ways only if there is a morally relevant difference between those people’s behavior. If each of two people are equally blameworthy for the same kind of transgression, then it would be unfair to blame only one but not the other. This applies even when one of those people is the blamer themselves, and therefore to hypocritical blame. Similarly, when running hypocritical theory, you treat yourself as deserving the sanctions that apply to others for unfair behavior, and there is no justification for this special treatment. Since it would be unfair for the rules of debate to make an exception for you to engage in some practice from which others should refrain, violations of the nonhypocrisy norm are therefore unfair.Even if these particular arguments fail as general accounts of what’s wrong with hypocritical blame, it’s clear that something is wrong with hypocritical theory in debate. Suppose that in their first round on some topic, some debater runs disclosure theory—i.e., the argument that all previously broken positions read in a debate must have been disclosed in advance—and so themselves have no broken positions to disclose, but have no intention of disclosing after this first round, and therefore never do. There is clearly something wrong with a world in which debaters can win on disclosure theory but then fail to disclose for the rest of the topic. The best explanation of this datum appeals to the nonhypocrisy norm: it’s wrong because it’s hypocritical theory. Similarly, something has gone wrong if a debater says that some aspect of their opponent’s methodology excludes marginalized individuals from debate and therefore warrants a loss, if they themselves go on to employ that same methodology in another round at the same tournament. And, similarly, something has gone wrong if someone runs the nonhypocrisy norm at the start of a tournament and then knowingly violates it in a later round, defending the violation as just part of the game. Generalizing from these examples, it seems that calling for the imposition of some penalty (e.g., a loss) as a response to violating what is or ought to be a rule for debate, or for otherwise undermining some values that are important to debate, warrants a kind of seriousness which hypocritical theory undermines. It is therefore reasonable to think that the nonhypocrisy norm is a good idea even if we don’t know what exactly is wrong with hypocritical theory and with hypocritical blame more generally. The onus is on the opponent of the nonhypocrisy norm to propose an alternative norm that prohibits hypocrisy in these particular examples in some nonarbitrary way without prohibiting hypocritical theory more generally, or to explain away the apparent compellingness of these examples.

3 Benefits of the Nonhypocrisy Norm

In this section, I argue that widespread acceptance of the nonhypocrisy norm would be good for the activity.

3.1 Decreasing frivolous theory

First, the nonhypocrisy norm would significantly lower the prevalence of frivolous or otherwise undesirable theory arguments. For example, since few would commit to conceding (or to contesting) the aff framework for an entire tournament, few would impose interpretations requiring their opponents to do so. Debaters could not alternate between two incompatible interpretations one of which is guaranteed to be violated, since they would then be guaranteed to violate the nonhypocrisy norm. This would greatly increase the amount of substantive debate because debaters would lose access to one-half of their incompatible binary interpretations for theory and topicality.The textbook disadvantage that must usually be weighed against a decrease in frivolous theory arguments is the discouragement of good theory arguments, which are key to preventing unfair practices. I myself see little evidence that good arguments would decline as the result of any proposed change in the evaluation of theory debates. But I think that is particularly unlikely to result from the nonhypocrisy norm, because the nonhypocrisy norm just requires you only to run theory arguments that you can live with. If we are worried about some good interpretation disappearing from the scene, then it should be one that debaters cannot live without, let alone can live with. So relevantly good interpretations would not be discouraged.

3.2 Side bias and other unfair advantages

Second, the nonhypocrisy norm would decrease side bias and prevent debaters from engaging in unfair practices better than the existing norms of theory debate, by selecting for better—i.e., fairer and more educational—interpretations. In the status quo, debaters have an incentive to engage in practices that advantage whatever side they happen to be on. The limits to this incentive are just the theory interpretations that they expect to lose to, against whatever opponent and in front of whatever judge they happen to have. But, as everyone knows, this is not really a function of which theory interpretations are actually best with respect to the actual promotion of fairness, education, inclusion, and other values of debate. It is largely a function of factors that have little to do with fairness and education: hours of practice and preparation on the relevant theory debates, knowledge of whatever arcane concepts were most recently invented by debaters, the reputation of the debater and their opponent, the opinions of the judge, what each debater had for breakfast, and so on. Debaters have a similar incentive to try to prevent others from engaging in practices that are, in fact, completely fair, simply because doing so (via theory argument) can win them the round.The nonhypocrisy norm would solve this issue by discouraging debaters from proposing interpretations that give one side an unfair advantage, because debaters would know that they would thereby disadvantage themselves about half the time. You would not want to engage in some practice that gives your side an unfair advantage, because you would then cede your future opponents’ right to engage in that same practice when it harms you. And you would not want to run theory against some practice that is perfectly fair, because you would then close off that option in your own future rounds. In expectation, then, debaters’ strategies would be more fair, because people could not get away with unfair strategies simply because their opponent in that round is worse at theory. An important consequence of this would be an expected decrease in side bias, since debaters would have an incentive to accept interpretations that give them a roughly equal chance of winning on both sides.Consider, for example, affirmative advocacies that are so narrow and plausible as to be nearly impossible to negate.2 Most debaters who hit such positions would resort to topicality, defending a perfectly sensible interpretation which rules out such narrow affirmatives. But many of these debaters then go on, when affirming, to defend affirmatives that are no (or barely) more general, and their opponents run the same topicality challenge against them. It is a vicious cycle of topicality against ridiculously specific affirmatives. The nonhypocrisy norm would force debaters to forgo one side of that topicality debate, or to find some interpretive middle ground that is mutually acceptable to both sides, and then—finally—to debate the resolution as they interpret it, thereby increasing fairness and substantive debate. Dealing with other hyperspecific affirmatives which you cannot plausibly negate or prepare to debate becomes the cost of running your own hyperspecific affirmative which your opponents cannot plausibly negate or prepare to debate.Or consider affirmative cases that are filled with ridiculous (or perhaps even incompatible) theory spikes. These spikes are designed to force the negative into an undesirable or even impossible strategic position. Refuting the spikes takes a lot of time away from debating the topic and requires an absurd amount of knowledge about arcane theoretical issues, which has massive opportunity costs in terms of substantive research. The nonhypocrisy norm would offer a simple and effective strategy against such cases, because the affirmative would never meet all of their ridiculous spikes when negating (or else they’d always lose). Indeed, this is a more promising strategy than directly answering those spikes or making other theoretical objections to the affirmative, because those strategies tend merely to invite new surprises—e.g., triggering latent conditions of other spikes—whereas it would be question-begging to leverage those spikes against the nonhypocrisy norm when they are merely further violations of it. In this way, the nonhypocrisy norm would decrease the net strategic utility and, therefore, prevalence of these unfair and largely uneducational strategies.

3.3 Improving theory debates

Third, the nonhypocrisy norm would improve the depth, quality, and evidential value of (as well as advocacy skills promoted by) theory debates. Until now, I have focused largely on the advantages of decreasing the prevalence of many theory arguments. But I’m not of the opinion that all theory debates are bad. I do, however, think that many theory debates in the status quo are bad. For example, theory interpretations are rarely (if ever) supported by empirical evidence or pedagogical theory. They are usually supported by hyperbolic predictions, inferred from the limited claimed experience of the debaters running them. It is sometimes claimed, for instance, that some practice makes it “impossible” for the aff or the neg to win, or makes debate so uneducational that few would want to engage in it, but I have never seen a reason to believe that such a claim is even close to true.Under the nonhypocrisy norm, however, the proof is in the pudding! The fact that someone is actually defending, say, two conditional counterplans, or that the aff must be topical under some interpretation of the topic, would provide at least some evidence that the practice or interpretation is sufficiently fair or educational to make it worth permitting or requiring throughout the tournament. Obviously this evidence is quite limited, and it’s far from a sufficient condition for some practice being legitimate or some interpretation being mutually beneficial (e.g., people would still have incentives to select interpretations that advantage themselves, at the expense of others, over the course of a tournament). But it at least injects more evidence and honesty into the debate than there ever exists in the status quo.Moreover, by discouraging a large number of meritless theory arguments, the nonhypocrisy norm would improve the depth of whatever education is provided by theory debates. The theory debates that remain would be serious intellectual disagreements between people who sincerely believe (or are, at least, willing to be governed by) their interpretations. Debaters would then have an incentive to prepare more deeply on a narrower range of theoretical issues, making the resulting theory debates more educational in ways that better train the debaters to advocate for their values in the activity. (See also Adam Torson’s “Debate and the Virtue of Intellectual Integrity.”)

4 Objections to the Nonhypocrisy Norm

What remains is a lengthy discussion of likely objections to the nonhypocrisy norm. I apologize for its length, but here is some justification for it.This article began as a highly speculative exploration of an unorthodox idea—not an idea that I thought particularly likely to be correct, but just an idea that seemed to me to have some important truth to it. But, after thinking about the objections that people would make, I became more confident that the idea was correct. Given this effect on my own attitudes towards the nonhypocrisy norm, I thought it might be worth including my thoughts on these objections for readers.

4.1 Switch-Sides Debate

Objection: “One great thing about debate is that you have to switch sides. So we must value the opportunity for people to defend both sides of an issue, even if they strongly disagree with one side. The nonhypocrisy norm discourages debaters from making arguments for conclusions that they personally reject.”

I agree that it’s important for debaters to defend both sides of the resolution. But it doesn’t follow that it’s important for debaters to defend both sides of every issue whatsoever. Sometimes there is more value in weighing the reasons on both sides and trying to come to the conclusion that is best supported by the balance of reasons—particularly, when that conclusion is about how you yourself should behave. Given that debaters switch sides on so many different issues (so that the value of switch-sides debate remains strong even under the nonhypocrisy norm), and there is at least some value in forming convictions on the basis of what you believe to be right, fair, and good, there is a unique educational advantage to introducing some test of conviction into some aspect of debate. Doing so would make debaters better advocates for change in their activity.However, it is also important to note that the nonhypocrisy norm doesn’t prohibit debaters from making arguments for conclusions they disagree with: their personal beliefs don’t directly enter into it. It prohibits them from defending rules that they themselves violate, whatever their opinions about it.If anything, the nonhypocrisy norm would likely improve switch-sides debate about the resolution. In the status quo, one can affirm and negate essentially different topics, by defending different interpretations of the resolution depending on which side you’re on. When affirming, you defend an interpretation that makes it easier to affirm; when negating, you defend an interpretation that makes it easier to negate. That’s just basic strategy, given the norms that govern the status quo. But this undermines much of the value of resolutional debate, because it lets you off the hook of having to both affirm and negate the very same proposition. The nonhypocrisy norm would improve the quality of resolutional debate by prohibiting debaters from changing the topic whenever they switch sides. (And it would do this without forcing debaters to engage in switch-sides debate if they have some principled reason to refrain.)

4.2 No Difference

Objection: “But what distinguishes theory interpretations from any other argument—e.g., the likely economic effects of the plan? Surely debaters should be able to debate both sides of those issues. Why not theory issues?”

The relevant difference is that you can’t be hypocritical, in the relevant sense, with respect to claims about the likely economic effects of the plan. Those claims don’t say that debaters should or should not do something that a debater might or might not have done. Of course, a debater’s personal behavior might constitute evidence that they don’t believe some empirical claim that they advance in a debate. But I don’t see what’s wrong with bringing such evidence into the picture and debating its significance. That pattern doesn’t involve hypocrisy in the sense I’ve been discussing, because it doesn’t involve blame for engaging in behavior that one engages in oneself.Some might worry that the nonhypocrisy norm would create a slippery slope to the cross-application of other arguments between different rounds, in undesirable ways. For example, it should obviously be irrelevant to the substance of a debater’s counterplan in some debate that they defended some permutation against it in another debate, when they were on the other side. But there is no reason why the nonhypocrisy norm would make such considerations relevant, since they don’t involve hypocritical theory. We would need some special reason (having nothing to do with the nonhypocrisy norm) to think that such considerations are relevant in order to count them as such; my arguments here provide no such reason. Nor do I think that any reason is forthcoming. We might have reason to consider a debater’s previous claim that p as evidence against their present claim that not-p if the reason to believe the present claim were simply because they said so (i.e., because they claim to be an authority on the question). For we would then have the same kind of reason on both sides. But few claims in debate are ever justified in that kind of way. Debaters usually provide arguments for their claims that appeal to evidence other than their own authority, and so their previous assertions provide no relevant evidence against their present ones. It is not obvious to me that, when debaters do try to justify claims by appeal to their own authority, their recent claims to the contrary should be off limits.

4.3 Moral Claims

Objection: “But some claims made in debates—e.g., moral ones—do apply to debaters, and so debaters can violate the moral norms that they themselves advocate. If, for example, the aff claims that everyone should do whatever maximizes aggregate welfare, then wouldn’t they be hypocritical in attending a debate tournament, which probably fails to maximize aggregate welfare?”

Although I agree that moral claims can have implications for what judges and debaters should do (see my “Where the Argument Leads”), there is an important difference between believing or asserting that an act is wrong and blaming someone for it. The claim that everyone should maximize aggregate welfare may entail that it’s wrong to compete in debate tournaments (given plausible empirical assumptions), but a proponent of that claim needn’t thereby blame people for competing in debate tournaments. Therefore, the impropriety of hypocritical blame doesn’t by itself entail any similar impropriety in believing or asserting that people ought to do things that you yourself don’t do.Moreover, even if there were a similar impropriety in that pattern, there doesn’t appear to be any reasonable penalty to impose in debates in which that occurs, because one hasn’t called for any penalty against people who fail to live up to the proposed obligation. The crucial difference is the absence of a violation/link, and of a penalty or other implication. These features make the practices I’m discussing relevantly different from other claims in debate.

4.4 Unverifiability

Objection: “Violations of the nonhypocrisy norm cannot be verified because it depends on some out-of-round event—i.e., the debater’s having violated or run an interpretation in some prior round.”

There are many ways to know that a debater has violated the norm. It might be revealed on the NDCA Wiki, or transmitted by testimony, or admitted by the debater in CX. (Hey, at the very least, this article might provide a new argument for disclosure theory: disclosure is key to verifying compliance with the nonhypocrisy norm.) Some might object that these measures are not perfect: people might lie in CX; disclosures might not reveal relevant violations; it’s impossible to check every round on someone’s wiki. That’s true. But even if enforcement is imperfect or even somewhat rare, the mere risk of losing to the nonhypocrisy norm would deter many people from violating it—just as the relatively small risk of getting caught violating norms of evidence ethics deters many people from miscutting cards. And there is, comparatively, little to no unfairness suffered in cases where violations are not caught, because those and many other violations would still happen in a world where the nonhypocrisy norm is rejected. (The objection is also not unique to the nonhypocrisy norm: almost no interpretations or even official rules would ever be perfectly.)Some might admit that everyone in the room might actually know that the nonhypocrisy norm has been violated but nonetheless claim that such knowledge is off limits. But most claims in debate are about out-of-round events. There is no reason to suppose that the only things that the debaters and judges can take to be known are the goings-on of their small room. If one debater says that humans have walked on the moon and the other denies it, let a a debate ensue. But absent solid evidence for the conspiracy theory, the judge ought to take as known what they and the students all know to be true.

4.5 Changing Our Minds

Objection: “Even if violations of the norm can be verified, you can’t verify that the violating debater has the objectionable pattern of attitudes that make hypocritical blame inappropriate. For example, the debater might have simply changed their mind in between the round where they proposed the interpretation and the round where they violated it. Changing one’s mind is a good thing and should be rewarded, not punished!”

I agree that changing our minds is particularly important for debaters (see, e.g., my “Changing Our Minds”). But here’s something better: not believing something unless one has sufficient evidence to conclude that it’s true. If a debater genuinely believes in one round that multiple conditional counterplans are bad, and genuinely changes their mind before running multiple conditional counterplans in the next round, coming to believe that they are perfectly fine, then the debater seems to have been overconfident at least one of those times. Better to suspend judgment until one has enough evidence to reach a conclusion that one can expect to remain stable for at least a weekend. Moreover, when a debater does form a belief on the basis of sufficient evidence and decides to adopt that interpretation throughout a tournament, the nonhypocrisy norm would give them more information that they can use to reevaluate the belief, and a greater incentive to actually change their mind in the event that they are wrong, since they would witness the effects of an interpretation over repeated trials (i.e., multiple rounds at a tournament).Moreover, the scenario we’re considering seems to me extremely uncommon. Outside of debate, we would expect that the person show remorse and apologize to whomever they now believe they wronged. If a debater does those things, then perhaps some reason for enforcing the nonhypocrisy norm would be diminished. But note that this objection only applies to the first kind of argument for the nonhypocrisy norm, regarding the general impropriety of hypocritical blame. It doesn’t apply to second first kind of argument, from its good effects. So its importance is limited.

4.6 Hyperspecialization

Objection: “Many debaters already hyperspecialize in one aspect of debate, which is bad for dialogue between debaters of different interests and ideologies. The nonhypocrisy norm would worsen this problem by forcing them to prepare for all rounds at a given tournament in the same way.”

I agree that hyperspecialization is a problem, because I think there is much to learn from all the different styles of debating. But debaters would still have competitive incentives to branch out under the nonhypocrisy norm, in a couple of ways. First, different styles of debate don’t necessarily require different interpretations of what debaters must or may not do in the course of a round. In fact, the nonhypocrisy norm better promotes dialogue between debaters of different interests and ideologies for the following reason: debaters could be expected to converge upon mutually acceptable (and fairly permissive) interpretations because, in the absence of knowledge about what their opponents will do, they would want to preserve the flexibility to run a wide array of different positions; there would then be greater clash between those positions, rather than evasion of those positions via theory interpretations (see my “Fear of Clash”). It is important to note here that the nonhypocrisy norm does not require debaters to run theory against arguments or practices that they don’t engage in themselves; it just requires them not to run theory against arguments or practices that they do engage in themselves. And, second, debaters would have incentives to adjust their interpretations over the course of each topic—e.g., after encountering some unforeseen effect at some tournament, or in order to prevent their opponents from predicting their next move. The nonhypocrisy norm only requires nonhypocrisy within a single tournament, and there’s no reason why shifting strategies within that time frame is uniquely important. Debaters would have at least as much of an incentive to diversify their strategies over the course of their debate careers as they currently have.

4.7 Gerrymandering

Objection: “The nonhypocrisy norm would simply encourage debaters to propose gerrymandered or hyperspecific interpretations when running theory so that they technically don’t violate their own interpretations. So the norm would not significantly reduce frivolous theory and would make theory debates in another way worse.”

This disadvantage is not particularly unique, because gerrymandered theory interpretations—i.e., interpretations that contain arbitrary conditions or which target arbitrary combinations of arguments, such as “In round 4 of the Harvard Tournament, the neg may not run X, Y, and Z, if they are also doing Q”—are already prevalent in the status quo. But actually I think that widespread adoption of the nonhypocrisy norm would likely reduce the gerrymandering of theory interpretations. For it would then be a glaring disadvantage of such interpretations that they unfairly allow their proponents to skirt the nonhypocrisy norm. That disadvantage would arguably outweigh the tiny advantage of such a narrow interpretation, so it would be easy to argue that gerrymandered interpretations are bad. Theoretical gerrymandering would therefore go down. Disadvantage: straight-turned.Gerrymandered interpretations could also be avoided in two other ways. They could be avoided, first, by a modified version of the nonhypocrisy norm: debaters must meet their own interpretations and relevantly similar interpretations for at least the entire tournament in which those interpretations are proposed; relevant similarity is determined by the reasons to prefer the interpretation. This prevents people from evading the nonhypocrisy norm by gerrymandering, without appealing to a sweeping “spirit of the interpretation” conception of violating theory. They can be avoided, second, by debaters emphasizing other disadvantages of gerrymandered interpretations. Here’s one example: a gerrymandered interpretation would, if widely accepted or internalized, make the activity significantly more confusing and difficult to learn in a way that has no compensating educational value, which would decrease participation; decreased participation harms not only those who don’t get the benefits of debate, but also the existing participants, because they would have fewer (and, in expectation, weaker) competitors to be challenged by and to learn from. So a possible rise in theoretical gerrymandering is not a reason to reject the nonhypocrisy norm.

4.8 Fun

Objection: “It’s fun and interesting to defend a wide variety of theory interpretations, even ones that aren’t particularly compelling. The nonhypocrisy norm would ruin some of this fun.”

Theory debates can be fun. But they can also be very much not fun for a lot of debaters (as well as judges)—particularly when the interpretation being defended is not something that anyone in the room actually thinks should be a rule for debate. The rampant use and abuse of cheap-shot theory arguments in LD has tempted (and probably led) many debaters to quit the activity altogether. And I see no reason to privilege the enjoyment that some derive from the activity as it is over the enjoyment that others would derive from the activity as it could be. You can have fun in debate in a lot of other ways, without ruining anyone else’s fun, while complying with the nonhypocrisy norm—including, I suspect, by defending the nonhypocrisy norm. The nonhypocrisy norm might even make theory debates more fun by incentivizing more nuanced and well-considered theory interpretations, rather than repetitive interpretations that few people take seriously enough to get excited about. So the nonhypocrisy norm seems to me worth trying out, even if only as an experiment.

4.9 The Basketball Analogy

Objection: “Debate theory is not relevantly like hypocritical blame. Making and voting on a ‘hypocritical’ theory argument is more like yelling at a basketball referee that you’ve been fouled on one play, and then intentionally fouling on the next. That’s just part of the strategy of the game—nothing wrong there.”3

I agree that some theory (and other “pre-fiat”) arguments lack the seriousness of moral blame—particularly when the impacts are merely to the competitive equity of the round at issue, and not to any seemingly higher values of the activity as a whole. And, although I know virtually nothing about any sport, it seems right that there is nothing inappropriate in the basketball example because the pattern of behavior is just part of the game. But the reason why this pattern is part of the game is because it’s built into the rules. Those rules can’t be changed by the players or referees mid-game, and they seem to be considered mutually acceptable by the players. But if the rules could be changed, as they effectively can in debate rounds, and if the players thought they had reason to, because they thought that intentional fouls and accusations of fouling were becoming problematic, then I think it could, in principle, be sensible to impose something like the nonhypocrisy norm with respect to fouling in basketball. Obviously I have no reason to think those conditions actually hold, so I’m not suggesting that such a norm actually be imposed in basketball. I’m just pointing out that debate is unlike basketball in certain ways—namely, by being governed by extremely malleable norms and because the behavior analogous to accusations of fouling and intentional fouling do seem undesirably rampant in debate—and that if basketball were more like debate in those ways, then a parallel proposal could possibly make sense in that context, too. Since the rules of our game are not fixed, we have little reason to take status-quo practices (e.g., insincere theory arguments) as given, or as having some privileged status, in the way that basketball players take their practices as given.The other side of this coin is that those who think frivolous theory is desirable in debate and that the current norms are mutually acceptable to everyone have little reason to support the nonhypocrisy norm, except perhaps in cases where the violations appear to carry greater moral seriousness than accusations of fouling in basketball. This view might be defended on the grounds that theory arguments, whatever their substantive merit as proposed rules for debate, require strategic thinking, which is valuable. But, given that all arguments in debate have strategic costs and benefits, there is no evidence that the particular theory arguments discouraged by the nonhypocrisy norm are uniquely key to strategic thinking. And the nonhypocrisy norm would introduce a new and particularly valuable dimension of strategic thinking into debate, because debaters would have to consider more long-term costs and benefits of adopting various interpretations.

4.10 No Expectation of Sincerity

Objection: “But what the basketball analogy reveals is that theory arguments are not intended or expected to be sincere in a debate. No one thinks that whenever someone advances a theory interpretation, it’s because they actually believe that interpretation. They, like all other arguments, are mere strategic tools. And this lack of an expectation of sincerity makes theory (and other pre-fiat) arguments relevantly distinct from blame.”4

I don’t think we do (or should or can) treat all arguments in a debate as mere strategic tools with no expectation of sincerity. I’ve given the example of disclosure theory, as well as arguments which equate some aspect of a debater’s performance with serious harm or wrongdoing. And if it’s agreed that some theoretical (or otherwise “pre-fiat”) advocacies are relevantly like hypocritical blame, then we have reason to accept the nonhypocrisy norm more generally, because there is no fundamental difference between those arguments and other theory arguments which don’t carry the same expectation. That reason is not decisive. But it means that, if the nonhypocrisy norm is to be rejected, then we would need to radically revise our attitudes towards the arguments I have mentioned (e.g., disclosure theory). Even if we could revise those attitudes, there would be significant costs to doing so: I think it would breed cynicism and apathy about efforts to improve debate from the ground-up—i.e., via debate about debate—and those efforts are the primary way in which theory debate trains students to become better advocates for change.But even if we had no expectation of sincerity (either for all arguments or for some set of theory arguments), this response would only address the first kind of justification for the nonhypocrisy norm (its grounding in more general norms against hypocritical blame), not the second kind (its good effects). And it magnifies that second kind of justification. For if proponents of theory interpretations do not in general believe them, this provides further evidence that the status quo is governed by interpretations that don’t promote good debate. Since proponents of a theory interpretation should be in a position to know the strongest arguments in their favor, the fact that one doesn’t believe that people should lose for violating one’s interpretation is good evidence that people should not lose for violating it. My claim here is not that there is anything morally wrong with insincere theory arguments, if there is no expectation that they be sincere; it’s that, to the extent that theory arguments are insincere, they’re more likely to be bad (i.e., unsound) arguments. And bad theory arguments are bad for debate, since they detract from clash about the proposition that all participants can (and should be expected to) prepare to debate beforehand, and because they unfairly penalize debaters for things that we have no reason to penalize, without any compensating increase in the fairness or educational value of debate. The nonhypocrisy norm would significantly decrease the prevalance of bad theory arguments by imposing a new strategic cost on advancing those arguments, and this impact is even more important if such arguments are rarely believed by their proponents.

4.11 Norm-Setting

Objection: “The arguments for the nonhypocrisy norm assume that the purpose of theory is to set community norms for the activity as a whole. But that’s false, because the vast majority of theory debates have no effect on community norms. So there is no reason to accept the nonhypocrisy norm.”5

Actually, none of my arguments assume that the purpose of theory is to set community norms. I have not made any assumptions about the purpose of theory, partly because I don’t think there is such a thing as “the purpose of theory.” Theory may very well have many different purposes: to rectify in-round unfairness, to promote educational or otherwise good debate, to allow debaters to vent their frustrations, to please Cthulu because he likes debate theory, and maybe some others—who knows? One of those might, or might not, be to set community norms. I don’t take a stance on that here.To see more precisely why my arguments do not assume a “norm-setting” conception of theory, we should be more precise about what such a conception entails. In debate rounds and out-of-round discussions, the label of “norm-setting” is often used to refer to two distinct and independent ideas; my arguments don’t assume either of them.6The first “norm-setting” view is a view about the reasons to vote (or drop the argument on) theory. The view is that the judge should vote on theory in order to deter future violations of the interpretation, thereby promoting fairness and education in other debates—as opposed to voting on theory in order to rectify unfairness in the present debate. This is the view that is (or would be) undermined by objections like, “Theory debates have little to no effect on community norms,” or “The judge lacks jurisdiction to consider effects on other rounds.” And this is the view that has been used to justify reverse voting issues via claims like, “If deterring violations of a good norm is a reason to vote for the norm, then encouraging violations of a bad norm is a reason to vote against the norm” (or something like that). I, therefore, believe that this first view has the strongest claim to the label of “norm-setting” (although, given the ambiguous usage in the status quo, some other label would likely be better).The second view that sometimes gets called “norm-setting” is a method of evaluating and applying interpretations, the spirit of which may be captured by (one meaning of) the slogan, “It’s not what you do; it’s what you justify.” The method is to figure out which interpretation would be best for debate in general, and then to apply the best interpretation to the present round to see if there’s a violation. But, crucially, the claim isn’t that the violation is necessarily unfair or uneducational; this method eschews direct evaluation of practices in terms of fairness or education in favor of evaluation of norms that would promote fairness and education. This kind of view raises concerns about the relevance of merely potential unfairness, but these concerns are quite different from the worries about the first “norm-setting” view discussed in the previous paragraph.I don’t know why exactly these two views are lumped together under the label of “norm-setting.” But one hypothesis is this: the second depends for its plausibility on the first. If the second view were correct, and the judge should penalize someone for a practice that violates a good norm but isn’t itself unfair, it would be hard to justify that punishment on any grounds other than deterrence. So the second view seems implausible if we reject the first. This may, in part, explain why people conflate the two views. But there may also be other reasons, which I won’t speculate about.In any case, let me now explain the principle to which some of my arguments do appeal, in order to see how it’s distinct from the “norm-setting” views above. What I have assumed, in arguing from the good effects of the nonhypocrisy norm, is that an in-round practice (namely, hypocritical theory) is in one respect unfair if it violates some norm (namely, the nonhypocrisy norm) whose widespread acceptance would be best for debate, or would be justifiable to all participants. This is a criterion or heuristic for evaluating the fairness of a practice, not a justification for voting against unfair practices. It is, therefore, distinct from the first “norm-setting” view. My argument from the good effects of the nonhypocrisy norm is not that the judge should vote against hypocritical theory in order to deter it in other rounds. It is not committed to the empirical assumption that theory debates shape community norms. The argument is, rather, that hypocritical theory is unfair because it violates a norm that ought to regulate all debates. I haven’t tried to explain why the judge should vote against unfair practices, but many different explanations are compatible with my arguments—including, for example, the view that the only reason to drop an argument or debater on theory is to rectify in-round unfairness: a practice might be unfair by virtue of violating some rule that ought to be a norm, even if penalizing the debater for that practice would not do much to bring about that norm.7The principle I have just stated is also distinct from the second “norm-setting” view, which asks the judge to punish debaters for practices which violate good norms even if those practices are not, in themselves, unfair. This view and mine may agree about which norms are good. But my principle adds that the judge should vote against the practice because it is unfair, and that it is unfair because it violates a principle that is mutually acceptable and beneficial to all participants. It is, therefore, not true of my principle that it justifies voting on merely potential unfairness, or voting against someone who debated fairly, or that it depends for its plausibility on the deterrent benefits of punishing someone with a loss.I have just explained why my arguments do not presuppose a problematic notion of “norm-setting.” But some might wonder why the nearby principle that I’ve assumed is correct. Why exactly should the good effects or justifiability of a norm, if widely accepted, bear on the unfairness of practices that violate that norm? That’s a big question, which I’m not fully prepared to answer here. But reasoning of this kind is not unfamiliar. It is perhaps clearest in contractualist reasoning about ethics (Scanlon 1998), but it also has much wider appeal. Whatever the merits of Kant’s broader ethical theory, his concern with the universalizability of our maxims captures the strong intuition that it’s wrong, because unfair, to make an exception of yourself (Korsgaard 1985). And many consequentialists evaluate fairness by looking at the effects of certain principles in situations of full compliance—even in nonideal contexts where most people don’t comply (Murphy 2000). And particularly in the context of an activity or community with common goods, such as fairness and education in debate, a participant’s failure to abide by principles whose widespread adoption would promote those common goods amounts to a kind of free riding, which is unfair (see Cullity 2008). My arguments, therefore, appeal to a familiar way of reasoning about fairness, not a contentious claim about the purpose of theory or the effects of voting on theory.Indeed, I find it hard to see how to reason about fairness in debate without appealing, in any respect, to the effects of an interpretation as a rule for the activity. Interpretations state requirements, prohibitions, or permissions for either one or both sides of the debate. But suppose the advocated interpretation is restricted only to the particular debate in which the interpretation is proposed. What explains why the relevant practice should be required, prohibited, or permitted in this debate but not in others? Why should your opponent have to do something in this debate that you and others should not have to do in other debates? Many philosophers follow Rawls (1999, 117) in imposing a “generality condition” on fairness, which rules out principles that are formulated using expressions like names (“Chris” and “TOC”), indexicals (“you” and “me”), and demonstratives (“this” and “that”) (see, e.g., Laden 1991). So if something is unfair in this debate, then it should also be unfair in other debates. There’s nothing special about any given debate from the perspective of fairness. (If there is some relevant feature about the circumstances of this debate that makes the practice uniquely unfair, then that should be baked into the interpretation—which remains advocated across debates—not as a restriction of the extent to which the interpretation is advocated.)This kind of reasoning—from the universal adoption of a norm, to the unfairness of practices that violate that norm—also seems essential to our understanding of why certain practices are unfair. Suppose that, for no particular reason, you read an affirmative on the wrong topic. You provided ample warning to your opponent, who is better prepared on that topic, but they did not consent to using the wrong topic. This practice, in this particular instance, arguably does not disadvantage your opponent or impede impartial adjudication of the debate. It doesn’t seem to have any particularly detrimental effects on the present round. Nonetheless, the practice is clearly unfair. It is unfair because, as a matter of principle—and for reasons I have defended elsewhere—the affirmative should generally be expected to defend the resolution (at least, by default, absent any good reason to depart from this rule). It might be objected that this kind of judgment could be captured by appealing to other in-round harms, such as harms to education. But we can imagine a version of the case in which there are no net harms to in-round education. And, more importantly, it’s absurd to suppose that one should lose or be penalized merely by virtue of making the debate less educational than it could’ve been, since no debate round has ever been as educational as it could’ve been. We can make sense of education as a theory impact, it seems, only by considering the educational effects of certain practices or rules on the activity as a whole. (In some sense, then, my view sees education as an “internal link” to fairness: the educational benefits of universally adopting a norm can make it unfair to violate that norm.) The fact that the present judge does not actually control the rules of other debates, and so cannot do much to secure those impacts to education, no more undermines the relevance of those impacts than the fact that we can’t control each other’s actions undermines rule consequentialism, Kant’s formula of universal law, or the Golden Rule.I have argued that it’s unfair to violate a norm that ought to govern all debates, and that this claim is distinct from the objectionable views that get called “norm-setting.” But it’s worth noting that the focus on other debates is, strictly speaking, dispensable for purposes of my argument. Although we have been reasoning about fairness in terms of the benefits of rules’ universal acceptance across rounds, we could also understand the fairness of a debate round in terms of the principles for the regulation of that round which both debaters would have reason to agree to under suitably impartial conditions. We can ensure such impartial conditions by imposing a kind of veil of ignorance. If you didn’t know which side you were on, what aspects of debate you’re best at, which aspects of the topic you researched most deeply, where you go to school, and so on, which principles would you have most reason to want to govern any given round? The imagined ignorance ensures impartiality along these dimensions, which is essential to a fair debate. The rules that you would have most reason to accept from behind this veil of ignorance are, I believe, the very same rules that would be best if universally accepted in all debates. That’s because the veil of ignorance essentially combines all these debates together into a single debate under uncertainty, since the present debate could, for all we know, turn out to be relevantly like any of those other debates; the probability of a practice being utilized in the present debate, conditional on being governed by a certain norm, reflects the frequency of that practice in possible future debates governed by that norm. In the presence of such uncertainty, we would have reason to minimize the risk of practices that advantage one side, or which supplant substantive education with frivolous theory debates, or which fail to treat all participants as moral equals, given that each debater has an interest in winning the round, in the educational value of the round, and in being treated with respect. We would, therefore, accept the nonhypocrisy norm (along with its proposed penalties), because the nonhypocrisy norm would decrease the prevalence of practices that compromise those interests. Violating the nonhypocrisy norm is, therefore, unfair, because we would have most reason to agree to its regulation of the present debate under suitably impartial conditions. This kind of reasoning moves from the expected benefits of a debate rule for participants to the unfairness of practices that violate that rule in a way that is obviously not committed to a “norm-setting” conception of theory.8I have sketched various possible accounts of why the goodness of a norm for the activity gives participants reasons of fairness to abide by that norm. Even if these accounts are ultimately rejected, it would be unreasonable to entirely dismiss the relevance of such considerations to debate theory. This is because, if such considerations were unable to justify the in-round imposition of theoretical interpretations, there would be little to no competitive incentive for students to debate in ways that are good for the activity. Costs and benefits to the activity, community, and its participants would nearly always give way to the more immediate competitive considerations of any given debate. I see no reason to embrace that unhappy state of affairs. Debaters and judges should feel empowered to promote positive changes in round via good theory arguments; otherwise, change is extremely unlikely to happen, and we’ll be stuck with a highly suboptimal status quo. It is therefore reasonable to consider the effects of theoretical norms to be reasons for or against the in-round imposition of such norms, even in the absence of a general theory that explains why they are such reasons.

4.12 The Better Debating

Objection: “The ballot asks who did the better debating. In context, that’s clearly about who did the better debating in this round. And violations of the nonhypocrisy norm are not relevant to that question, because they are about what happens in other rounds.”

Violations of the nonhypocrisy norm are not (at least entirely) out-of-round violations. A debater must violate the nonhypocrisy norm in the round in which it’s run, either by violating a previous interpretation in this debate or by advancing an interpretation in this debate that one failed to meet in a previous round. Although such violations depend on out-of-round conditions, there is no violation without some relevant event happening in the present debate, and that in-round event is the violation itself. So the violation cannot be ruled out as in principle irrelevant to who did the better debating in the present round. And, more generally, it cannot be objectionable that the violation depends on some out-of-round conditions, because many arguments depend, in some way, on out-of-round conditions: topicality depends on some resolution having been selected by the NSDA and tournament; evidence ethics depends on some evidence reflecting what’s published in the world; politics disadvantages depend on what’s going on in Washington.The objector might grant that out-of-round events can legitimately bear on the present round, while denying that hypocritical theory bears on the present round in the right way. For it might be thought that violations of the nonhypocrisy norm do not confer an advantage on the violating debater, understood as some factor which makes it easier for them to defend their side of the resolution, and which therefore allows them to win without doing the better debating. On one conception of theory, that is the only relevant kind of unfairness.But violating the nonhypocrisy norm does involve such an advantage, because the debater who violates the nonhypocrisy norm employed a strategic option (either the theory argument or the thing that violates it) to which they shouldn’t have had access. Access to that argument is an advantage relative to not having access to it, and they shouldn’t have that advantage for the reasons I’ve already explained. So they might win without doing the better debating, by virtue of having that unmerited advantage.Hypocritical theory is an advantage not only relative to the normative baseline of what the debater ought to have access to, but also relative to the opponent’s strategic assets, when one debater complies with the nonhypocrisy norm. Assuming that the violation of the nonhypocrisy norm is unique, the debater who meets it lacked access to certain strategic assets (namely, all positions which violate any interpretation they have proposed or may wish to propose later in the tournament, and all interpretations that would be violated by any position they have run or may wish to run later in the tournament) to which their opponent had access. So the violator of the nonhypocrisy norm has an easier route to the ballot than the nonviolator. And that advantage is unfair because it derives from a practice that ought to be prohibited.It might be replied that meeting the nonhypocrisy norm was that debater’s choice; they could have violated it instead, and then the advantage would’ve been equal. But this is just the “reciprocity” objection to theory against multiple a prioris and necessary-but-insufficient burdens, which is widely and rightly rejected. The problem with the reciprocity objection is that it does not satisfy fairness for both sides to have been able to engage in some practice if (a) one side did not actually engage in that practice, and (b) they had strong impartial reasons to refrain from engaging in that practice. (b) seems necessary because willingly sacrificing some strategic asset that one’s opponent utilizes should not, by itself, constitute an unfair advantage if there was no good reason for the sacrifice. In the case of multiple a prioris and necessary-but-insufficient burdens, the good reason might be that both sides’ engaging in that practice would be bad for debate. These conditions hold for the nonhypocrisy norm, since the debater who meets that norm has not engaged in hypocritical theory, and for good reason, since hypocritical theory is bad for debate.Maybe the unfair advantages in these cases don’t skew the substantive debate so badly that winning substance (even with the argument dropped) would provide zero evidence of doing the better debating, in which case the implication should maybe be dropping the argument rather than the debater. But if that’s the threshold for dropping the debater, I don’t think any theoretical violation has ever met it.The “better debating” standard might be thought relevant in yet another way. I have compared hypocritical theory to hypocritical blame. In both cases, there is a kind of penalty or harm imposed or called for. But some might argue that theory is relevantly unlike blame because dropping the argument or debater is not a kind of penalty; it’s just a way of correcting the skew caused by arguments that make it easier for one side of the resolution.But the fact that one debater could win the substantive debate without necessarily doing the better debating obviously does not show that they did the worse debating. So why should the result of theory be a loss for the debater who caused the substantive skew, rather than some other method of resolution—e.g., a coin flip? The reason is presumably that a loss is a penalty or harm (and the win a prize or benefit), which the judge has reason to distribute fairly rather than unfairly. There is an asymmetry between the two debaters—the skew is one debater’s fault, not the other’s—which makes it fairer to penalize the debater who caused it than to penalize the debater who suffered it. This makes it unfair to distribute that penalty by chance—e.g., via coin flip— because the debater who suffered the skew would have grounds for complaint if they lose. The debater who caused the skew, by contrast, would have no grounds for complaint if they lose, because they are (in some sense) culpable for the situation. So we do think of a loss via theory as something like a penalty, even if the reasons to impose it are not deeply retributive. If we don’t think of it this way, it’s hard to see why the debater who caused the skew should lose, rather than giving both debaters an equal chance via a coin flip.The objector might reply that the judge should vote against the debater who caused the skew because they were shown to be the worse debater, by virtue of losing the theory debate. But that would seem to overgeneralize to all theory arguments, including ones that should intuitively be drop the argument, and including the nonhypocrisy norm, because there’s no reason to think that winning the theory debate is the best available evidence of better debating in some cases but not in those.The “better debating” standard, therefore, does not undermine my arguments for the nonhypocrisy norm.

5 Conclusion

I have argued that a norm against hypocritical theory would be good for debate. I suspect that many readers will find this claim to be obviously false. That puzzles me: maybe it’s false, but it’s not obviously false. I suspect that hypocritical theory seems so clearly legitimate to many people at least partly because it is such a deeply entrenched practice in the contemporary norms of national circuit debate, and the nonhypocrisy norm will seem so obviously false to many people at least partly because it is so at odds with those norms. When debate dogma is challenged, many debaters and judges seem to be strongly biased in favor of the status quo. I think this bias is largely irrational, because debate norms emerge from some combination of competitive patterns and other arbitrary factors that we have little reason to expect to converge to a maximally fair and educational activity. Post hoc defenses of those norms often seem to me to have the character of rationalization rather than justification. Challenges to debate orthodoxy can only be given a fair hearing if we proactively try to counteract this bias. Even if we are not sure that hypocritical theory is bad, we have some reason to at least temporarily default to accepting the nonhypocrisy norm, because the advantages of openminded experimentation with debate norms outweigh the minor and unproven risks of deviating from the status quo, at least on the margin. We should always be questioning the conventional wisdom of national circuit debate, including the present focus on the individual round as the only relevant unit of advocacy.9

References

Cullity, Garrett. 2008. “Public Goods and Fairness.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (1): 1–21. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048400701846491.
Fritz, Kyle G., and Daniel Miller. 2018. “Hypocrisy and the Standing to Blame.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (1): 118–39. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12104.
Hart, H. L. A. 1959. “The Presidential Address: Prolegomenon to the Principles of Punishment.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 60: 1–26.
Hooker, Brad. 2003. Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality. Oxford; New York: Clarendon Press.
Korsgaard, Christine M. 1985. “Kant’s Formula of Universal Law.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66 (1-2): 24–47.
Laden, Anthony. 1991. “Games, Fairness, and Rawls’s A Theory of Justice.” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 189–222.
Loland, Sigmund. 1999. “Justice and Game Advantage in Sporting Games.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2 (2): 159–78. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1009960012546.
Murphy, Liam B. 2000. Moral Demands in Nonideal Theory. Oxford Ethics Series. New York: Oxford University Press.
Rawls, John. 1955. “Two Concepts of Rules.” Philosophical Review 64 (1): 3–32.
———. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
———. 2008. Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Wallace, R. Jay. 2010. “Hypocrisy, Moral Address, and the Equal Standing of Persons.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 38 (4): 307–41. https://www.jstor.org/stable/40926873.

  1. It’s worth noting, though, that topicality need not have the structure of blame. Topicality could instead be used to refocus the debate on a proposition other than the affirmative advocacy. This would require the negative to negate that proposition in order to win the debate, and would allow the affirmative to use applicable AC offense to try to affirm the new proposition. That kind of topicality argument is not a form of blame or a call for punishment, and so cannot be hypocritical in the relevant sense. I am sympathetic to the idea that topicality should, at least in many circumstances, take this nonpunitive form.
  2. I owe this insight, and the one in the next paragraph, to Jackson Lallas.
  3. Thanks to Chris Theis for pressing this objection.
  4. Thanks to Nina Potischman for pressing this objection.
  5. Thanks to Lavanya Singh and Jack Wareham for pressing this objection (and the next).
  6. I owe the disambiguation in the next five paragraphs to Marshall Thompson.
  7. Here’s another, perhaps more fitting, justification for voting against unfair practices: fairness requires judges to penalize practices shown to be unfair, because universal acceptance of a norm requiring judges to penalize unfair practices would be best for debate. The very same principle that prohibits hypocritical theory would then require voting against it. And this principle, as before, does not assume that the judge’s action has effects on other rounds. It assumes only that the judge must be fair, and that violating a principle whose universal acceptance would best promote fairness and education in debate is itself unfair. For a more general principle of which this is an instance, see Hooker (2003, 51). For a quite different justification for penalizing unfair practices, see Loland (1999), especially sections 5 and 6.
  8. I should mention that although my strategy in this section has been to show how my arguments do not assume a “norm-setting” view, there is perhaps something to be said for such views. First, even though most theory debates do not shape community norms, some do. The mere threat of losing on disclosure theory, for example, has significantly increased the prevalence of disclosure. The nonhypocrisy norm would have a particularly strong effect because it affects the incentives of both potential violators and potential proponents, since one can run the argument successfully only by complying with it (and, therefore, one’s other interpretations) throughout the tournament. Second, many of the objections to the first “norm-setting” view misunderstand the shape and role of deterrence in justifying punishment (see Rawls (1955) and Hart (1959)), although making good on this thought would require another article.
  9. My thinking about these issues benefited from conversations with many people, including Ishan Bhatt, John Boals, Sekou Cisse, Rex Evans, Jackson Lallas, Daiya Massac, Jacob Nails, Raffi Piliero, Nina Potischman, Lavanya Singh, Nick Smith, Chris Theis, Kathy Wang, Jack Wareham, participants in an evening seminar at VBI 2018, and especially Marshall Thompson. I regret that I haven’t been able to address all of their comments here.

 

A Critique of Full Text Disclosure by Ishan Bhatt and Rex Evans

The views and opinions expressed in this article are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of Victory Briefs.Ishan Bhatt was the 2018 NSDA National Champion and competes in Lincoln-Douglas Debate at St. Andrew’s Episcopal School in Mississippi. Rex Evans was a finalist at the 2018 Tournament of Champions and competes in Lincoln-Douglas Debate at Santa Monica High School in California. The authors would like to thank Lawrence Zhou and Paras Kumar for their valuable input and help.

A Brief Anecdote from Ishan

I remember when “must disclose full text” first started making the rounds at TOC my sophomore year and how quickly, just to avoid the theory debate, people started full text disclosing their evidence. I heard about it after round 2 and I made all of my TOC disclosure full text immediately. Soon after, full text disclosure was increasing exponentially.Last year, I was writing case negs for a round robin and realized that the full text disclosure of a particular aff was hard to read. Like, really hard to read. The plan was in the middle of an enormous block of text and theory arguments at the bottom were all mushed together. I also realized that the NDCA wiki, on the cites entry page, says pretty explicitly:“You should NOT paste full text cards here, only cites - if you want to disclose open source, upload a document on the next page as well.”Since I didn’t have any real DAs to the aff I was preparing for, I decided to write a quick theory shell with standards about the difficulty of reading full text and a hilariously bad ethical argument about following NDCA rules backed up by a promise-keeping deont card I swiped from Circuit Debater. However, round robins being round robins, I didn’t exactly get the panel I needed for my brilliant new theory argument, so I ended up never breaking it.At some point this year, Rex brought up his frustrations with this terrible practice and asked whether we should write a shell. I sent the shell I had written, and Rex read it in a couple rounds. But, since we both noticed a large amount of debaters still disclosing in this manner, we decided to move beyond 1ac theory arguments and actually write an article against what we believe is an easily fixable problem and articulate what we believe people should do instead.

Thesis

Debaters, if they choose to disclose the full text of their evidence, should upload a document with that evidence in the open source section of the disclosure page. In the citation box, debaters should disclose the first five words and last five words of the card. This article covers four issues. First, why full text disclosure evidence is good. Second, why putting that full text in the cites box is bad and why one should open source. Third, we preempt potential objections and evaluate the pros and cons of these claims. And fourth, we offer some miscellaneous thoughts on disclosure.

Section 1: Why Debaters Should Disclose the Full Text of their Evidence

This section independently addresses whether full text disclosure of evidence is a good practice in the first place. Our main argument deals with how debaters should disclose the full text of evidence if they choose to do so, but this section provides a brief primer on some of the justifications for full text disclosure we find most persuasive.Sub-Point A: Ease of AccessOpen source makes it easier for debaters to find evidence. Often it is difficult to find the original evidence because URL links are broken or paywalls prevent many debaters from accessing the original work. Not all debaters have access to the databases that some of us are lucky enough to have. In a world where debaters do full text disclose, the community no longer has to control F the first three/last three words of the evidence in question and then read through all of the article. Full text allows the evidence to be readily accessible for scrutiny, just one click away.Sub-Point B: Scrutiny of EvidenceOpen source incentivizes better card cutting because every competitor knows that it is extremely easy to scrutinize all of their evidence. It is difficult, absent full text, to find every single card in a 1AC independently, especially with limited time before debates. With full text, it’s all there in one place, easy to read. That means all the evidence can be scrutinized with one click, which incentivizes debaters to cut better and more ethically. Even if there wasn’t a malicious miscutting committed on the part of the debater, mistakes, discrepancies, and general problems with the evidence are much easier to find under our norm.Sub-Point C: Evidence “Stealing” is Not Bad.We think that debaters’ preoccupation with “evidence stealing” is misplaced because simply cutting a card does not make it someone’s property. Debaters, if reading another debater’s evidence, should indeed keep that debater’s initials at the end. However, the act of reading another debater’s card is something we should encourage, not prevent. Our stance does not mandate open source disclosure with highlighting, which means debaters would still have to re-highlight the evidence. There is no reason to force debaters to jump through extra hoops since the evidence is already out there. It’s better to share resources with everybody. This model would substantially lower entry barriers since teams without much infrastructure could also rely on a wealth of evidence provided by the wiki. Younger debaters, particularly those without deep coaching or backfiles, already use free internet resources to learn debate. Providing them with easy access to evidence allows to them to keep up with the amount of evidence required to be successful on the circuit.

Section 2: Why Debaters Should Open Source Their Evidence

If a debater chooses to post the full text of their evidence, they should not post it in the cites box, but should upload a document instead.Sub-Point A: Pre-Round PreparationReading through massive blocks of text in the cites box makes it substantially harder for debaters to prepare effectively before debates where time is a limited resource. It’s often difficult to isolate where a card ends and the next tag begins, and cards often take up so much space that more time is spent scrolling than actually reading tags, plan texts, standard texts, etc. It makes it significantly harder to isolate crucial portions of the affirmative such as advocacy texts or framing mechanisms which means debaters have to waste time figuring out where the aff says stuff instead of figuring out what the affirmative actually says. The wiki is meant to facilitate clash through transparency. Debaters should be able to access it and get right to work on creatively and thoroughly devising arguments against their opponents. A debater preparing to debate a specific affirmative should be able to both skim the affirmative case’s general thesis and tags while also assessing the evidence if they so choose. This optimizes the ability of the negative to prepare an in-depth attack on the affirmative, further facilitating the clash that disclosure is meant to create.Sub-Point B: Obfuscation of TricksThis also makes it easier to hide tricks in cases. For the purpose of this article, a trick is a short analytic that is out of place in the case and has a large impact in the round such as a “1ar theory lexically prior” blip right after a card ends and blended with the tag of the next card, or a “CX checks” spike in the middle of a utilitarianism framework. We are aware that this definition doesn’t have an exact bright-line but it’s sufficient for our argument - regardless of a specific definition of “tricks,” first 5 last 5 better deters debaters from hiding arguments that seek to evade debating over core issues and promote trickery over rigorous clash. These one-line arguments are easy to hide in large amounts of text, especially since our eyes are likely to skip over them when searching for the next paragraph break. Allowing debaters to scrutinize their opponents’ positions effectively weeds out terrible arguments, which fosters argument responsibility and leads to more educational clash over core issues. Independent of the educational value of these arguments, hiding them within the disclosure page is still net negative. If it is the case that debates should be over these arguments, then one should want one’s opponent to better prepare for each and every single trick.Sub-Point C: Processing IssuesMassive blocks of text can be difficult for people in the debate community with disabilities such as dyslexia, who have trouble reading through big blocks of text. We personally know a few debaters who can’t manage to look/focus on large blocks of unformatted text hard enough to discern various arguments and have heard similar things from other debaters. It is not acceptable to have a portion of the debate community to be unable to read through disclosure, especially since disclosure is meant to provide equal access to arguments.Sub-Point D: NDCA RulesLastly, the NDCA wiki asks you to do it. They made the wiki and have been running it for years. They know what good disclosure looks like and they know the cites box can get very cluttered. They don’t want their wiki filled with enormous jumbles of blocks of text. So, they explicitly tell you not to do it! There is probably some obligation to minimally follow the rules of the NDCA wiki. When you are voluntarily participating in some activity, you should be obligated to follow its rules unless you have a very strong reason not to. You have decided to disclose on their page, and they provide this service for the debate community for free - at least follow the rules they explicitly detail.Even if you aren’t persuaded by our appeal to NDCA rules, this argument still does one very important thing: it makes the norm we advocate for predictable and non-arbitrary. The wiki we’re disclosing on has a codified rule about our norm, so the burden is on those who violating to proactively justify why breaking that rule is good.

Section 3: Potential Objections

In an ideal world, everyone would stop full text disclosing in the cites box and start open sourcing just because this article dropped, and both of the authors were extremely qualified middle school Public Forum debaters. However, we don’t think this is the case. In light of this and after careful consideration, we do endorse reading theory against folks who full text in the cites box. Therefore, we’ve divided this section into two sub-sections. The first one will answer potential objections to our norm. The second will answer potential objections to reading theory to promote our norm.

Sub-Point A: Norm Objections

Objection 1: It’s just easier to copy/paste the 1AC into the cites boxFirst, ease should not primarily determine disclosure norms. Yes, it may be easier to copy/paste, but you know what’s also easier? Not disclosing at all! We think that slight difficulty of disclosing does not outweigh the obfuscation of full text disclosure. Norms aren’t always the easiest to abide by, but efficiency should never be the determiner of disclosure norms, much less when it takes about 30 seconds to use verbatim to wikify and then copy paste. If substantially better disclosure norms come at the cost of an extra minute or two, that’s a sacrifice that we as a community should be willing to make.Second, accessibility is more important than ease. Even if it takes you a little bit of extra time to abide by our norm, it’s worth it if it means that certain debaters are able to more meaningfully participate in the activity.Third, it’s not that hard - just make a doc and clear all the cards using verbatim. It would only take about 1 or 2 minutes to create this and we think it is worth the tradeoff. Uploading a speech document is extremely easy and if you don’t want to go through the work of unformatting the cards, don’t! If you’re all about ease, then we’re happy to see you disclose open source with all that highlighting that was just too hard to delete.Objection 2: It’s easier to view full text, open source requires downloading a docDisclosing in the cite box and disclosing open source are not mutually exclusive. We still think you should disclose tags and first 5/last 5 in the cites box - that makes it easier for those who want to just look at positions to do so and those who want to scrutinize your evidence can download documents. However, full text harms both of those objectives - people can’t isolate/examine evidence nor can they prep pre-round with huge blocks of text.Objection 3: People will just steal my cardsFirst, this objection doesn’t make much sense because debaters are still full texting either way, it’s just a question of where they full text (i.e. cite box or open source), so other debaters would still have the same ability to steal cards.Second, if one is claiming that debaters can’t steal evidence if one full texts because full text makes evidence more difficult to sort through, then it proves our point about it being obfuscatory.Third, we don’t think this is a problem - see Section 1.

Sub-Point B: Theory Objections

Objection 1: Won’t set a normFirst, this is the objection we disagree with the most. Disclosure theory in particular sets norms more broadly and quickly than pretty much any other theory argument. LD’s transition to almost universal disclosure certainly proves. The current full text industrial complex only took about a couple of months and about three large tournaments, which is particularly impressive considering only a few people read full text theory. At the start of the 2017-18 season, we observed that Strake Jesuit read “must disclose full text” almost every chance they got and debaters who lost to this theory argument began full texting and began reading theory themselves, until most of the circuit was disclosing full text. Multiple top debaters, such as Brentwood’s WJ and Lake Highland Prep’s MK, added notes to their wiki, explaining:“I've begun disclosing full text of carded evidence. All generics and evidence read on JANFEB will be full text disclosed. However, given I started this just now, my prep concerning SEPOCT and NOVDEC are disclosed using first three last three. If you would like the full text of this evidence just message me."While this is just one instance, there are numerous similar examples on the wiki that illustrate a widespread transition towards full texting evidence. Since transitioning from full text to uploading an open source doc is much more agreeable than transitioning from no full text to full text, we think our norm will actually spread faster.Second, we feel it is easier for theory to set norms on out-of-round practices than in-round practices. For example, we are aware that neither the “reverse voting issue” or “conditionality bad” has substantially reduced the number of theory arguments or conditional counterplans. This, we believe, is because in-round competitive incentives push debaters to still read these arguments. The 1NC is significantly more strategic if the counterplan is conditional or if one is able to read a topicality argument. Those differences could win or lose the round! However, our norm is such an easy practice to shift to with little to no detriment to one’s ability to win rounds, that debaters will likely change due to theory being read.Objection 2: Not enough abuse to loseYes, there is. We hope Section 2 should have persuaded you how terrible full texting in the cites box is for debate. Even if you did not find that material as persuasive as we did, the substance tradeoff of a few rounds with this shell would be small enough that the disadvantages to full texting in the cites box would outweigh. Remember, disclosure interps set norms extremely quickly, so this theory argument should ideally only have to be read a few times.We don’t endorse a 1% risk of offense model of theory debate where all the initiator has to do is win any slight risk that their interpretation better. This is usually because the substance tradeoff does not outweigh voting on the theory argument. For example, the educational value of a debate should not be lost because of the marginal abuse to “must spec status” or “font size theoryTM.” However, we think this objection does not apply to our norm for two reasons:Our norm is incredibly predictable since it is detailed in the guidelines of the NDCA wiki. Typically, most theory objections that entail marginal abuse, including the examples given above, are extremely ad hoc. They would allow a debater to “shift the goalposts” every round and win on some more marginal abuse. “Must not have fonts smaller than 8” can shift to “10” and then to “11.” However, since our norm is codified and predictable, we feel as if voting on a theory argument about it is not as egregious.We have established with Objection 1 that on questions of disclosure there is an opportunity to set real community norms that meaningfully improve the activity, so even if the offense for our disclosure norm is minimal the amount of abuse it’s adoption would resolve in the long-term outweighs a slight initial detriment to substantive education.Objection 3: not my responsibility/ask me to upload open source before the roundFirst, the NDCA rules argument, we think, destroys this objection. There are codified, predictable rules displayed prominently in the “cites” portion of the disclosure page of the wiki. If you’ve ever disclosed on the wiki before, you should have seen this rule.Second, if you’re willing to upload a document if asked, why not go ahead and do it? We totally understand putting off tasks until they’re staring at you in the face, but given that your practices could cost you a round at worst and cause you a theory headache at best, why not go ahead and change your practices?Third, our pre-round/pre-tournament preparation argument isn’t solved by the “asking” condition because it would require contacting everyone and then hoping they upload a document. If a debater breaks a position at Greenhill, it shouldn’t be till a few days before Marks that people are able to read the disclosure entry.Fourth, pairings are often released 30 minutes before the round, which doesn’t give debaters that much time to find their opponent’s Facebook, send a friend request, wait for the friend request to be accepted, send a message asking them to disclose an open source doc, and wait for the case to be open sourced. A debater shouldn’t have to waste a third of their prep time before the round at minimum (and that’s being generous), just to get what they should’ve had all along--an easily readable and accessible disclosure.Fifth, we believe that accessibility norms are better improved when debaters are proactive about good practices. Our argumentation in previous portions of this article details the positive benefits of our norms. A community-wide transition to these norms is much easier when debaters are proactive about their practices. We have explained why it would be easier, better for debate, and more accessible for our norm to be adopted - debaters actively embracing positive responsibility for better norms would substantially improve disclosure.Objection 4: My coach/team policy is against this normFirst, we don’t think this objection makes any sense in the context of our norm. If you already full text disclose, there is no reason your coach would not allow you to full text with an open source document.Second, this argument is not a reason to reject our norm. Just because it’s team policy doesn’t make the choice immune from criticism. Our argument is a reason your team policy should change. Imagine if one’s team policy required them to have incomplete cites or their coach insisted on forcing them to read contingent standards. If a debater lost to theory because of either of those choices, “my coach made me do it” might explain why they chose to engage in those practices, but they should have still lost that round.

Section 4: Misc. Thoughts/Musings

We think that debaters, even if they open source, should disclose first five/last five in the cites box so people can peruse your positions more casually and can get a brief idea of the plan/framework/advantages without having to download a document. Uploading cites boxes also lets each person get a snapshot of what your argumentative history on a topic is. Seeing “Kant 1AC, States 1AC, Deportations 1AC” on the wiki allows easy access to preparation.If you decide to continue full texting your evidence, please at the very least use the “====TAG====” function in order to bold your taglines and important parts like the plan and key analytics. This makes figuring out the structure of the position so much easier. It allows a natural break in the text that ensures your opponents can parse through your material.Please open source!---- Ishan and Rex

Existential Bare Plurals and Quantifier Scope by Jake Nebel

The views and opinions expressed in this article are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of Victory Briefs.Jake Nebel is a PhD candidate in philosophy at New York University, executive director at Victory Briefs, and (starting fall 2019) assistant professor of philosophy at the University of Southern California.Let’s start with some background. “Authoritarian regimes” is a bare plural: it’s a plural noun phrase without an explicit determiner (e.g., “five,” “some,” “all,” “the,” “most”). Bare plurals are typically used to express generic generalizations, as in “Ravens are black.” Unlike universally quantified statements, generics tolerate exceptions. For example, “Ravens are black” is true even though “All ravens are black” is false.In addition to generic readings, bare plurals can also sometimes have existential readings, as if they were preceded by “some.” For example, “Ravens are outside” is true just in case there are some ravens—i.e., more than one—outside. Unlike existential statements, generic generalizations are not entailed by specific instances. For example, the generic “Ravens are white” is false even though some ravens are indeed white; white ravens are white not because they are ravens but because they have leucism.For reasons I’ve given elsewhere, and which apply straightforwardly to this topic, I think “authoritarian regimes” is a generic bare plural, not an existential one. My reasons include (i) that it fails the upward-entailment test for existential bare plurals (the resolution doesn’t entail that the United States ought not provide military aid to governments, even though all authoritarian regimes are governments); (ii) that bare plurals denote kinds of things, not specific members of those kinds, and so get an existential reading only in very specific circumstances which don’t seem to obtain in this resolution; (iii) that generics are our default means of generalization, especially in moral contexts, so we should expect the resolution to be generic absent strong evidence to the contrary; and, most importantly, (iv) that we can simply tell that it’s generic by linguistic intuition, which is the primary source of data for linguistic theorizing.The generic interpretation implies that many affirmative advocacies—those that specify particular authoritarian regimes to which the United States ought not provide military aid, leaving open the possibility of providing aid to all other authoritarian regimes—do not affirm the resolution, because generic generalizations are not entailed by specific instances.1 To affirm the resolution, regime-specific affirmatives require an existential interpretation of “authoritarian regimes,” which is incorrect. In this article, however, I want to suppose for the sake of argument that the existential interpretation is correct, and argue that regime-specific affirmatives—even those that specify more than one regime—still violate the existential interpretation. In the course of laying out the argument, we’ll learn about an idea of crucial importance to both philosophy and linguistics—the concept of quantifier scope—and, rather than finish my dissertation, I’d like to introduce debaters to that idea.To introduce the concept of scope, consider the sentence,

  1. Every student read some book.

This sentence is ambiguous between two interpretations. On one interpretation, (1) says that there is some book b such that, for every student s, s read b. On this interpretation, the universal quantifier “every” is within the scope of the existential quantifier “some”; the existential quantifier has wider scope than the universal quantifier. This wide-scope interpretation of “some book” requires every student to have read the same book. On another interpretation, (1) says that, for every student s, there is some book b such that s read b. On this interpretation, the existential quantifier is within the scope of the universal quantifier; the existential quantifier has narrower scope than the universal quantifier. This narrow-scope interpretation of “some book” allows each student to have read a different book.Let’s apply this distinction to the existential interpretation of “authoritarian regimes.” The question is: what is the scope of the allegedly existential “authoritarian regimes” with respect to “ought not”? If it takes narrow scope, the resolution would mean roughly the same thing as,

  1. It ought not be the case that there are authoritarian regimes to which the United States provides military aid.

On this reading, the affirmative has to argue that there ought to be no authoritarian regimes to which the U.S. provides aid. Not only does the narrow-scope reading not allow the affirmative to specify a particular set of authoritarian regimes; it requires the affirmative to advocate something with respect to all authoritarian regimes. This is even stronger than the generic reading! This happens, in short, because the negation of an existentially quantified statement (it’s not the case that some x is F) is the universal generalization of a negation (every x is not F—i.e., no x is F). Regime-specific affirmatives therefore violate the narrow-scope reading.By contrast, on a wide-scope reading, the resolution would mean roughly the same thing as,

  1. There are authoritarian regimes such that it ought not be the case that the United States provides military aid to those regimes.

This convoluted claim is not exactly an attractive interpretation of the resolution. For one thing, there already are authoritarian regimes to which the United States doesn’t provide military aid, so the resolution surprisingly recommends a state of affairs that already obtains. But, more importantly, (3) is just obvious and uncontroversial. Who seriously denies that there are some authoritarian regimes to which the United States shouldn’t provide military aid? It is prima facie extremely unlikely that the intended or actual meaning of a debate resolution would be an obvious and uncontroversial proposition that recommends the status quo.Unlikely, yet not impossible, you might say. But there’s a much bigger problem for the wide-scope existential reading: existential bare plurals just can’t take wide scope. It is independently and cross-linguistically established that existential bare plurals can only receive narrow scope readings; they do not give rise to scope ambiguities. Consider, for example,

  1. Every student read philosophy books.
  2. Sam did not read philosophy books.

In these sentences, the bare plural “philosophy books” is existential, not generic. We might therefore expect that, like “some book” in (1), it could take either narrow or wide scope with respect to the universal quantifier in (4) and the negation operator in (5). But it can’t. It can only take narrow scope. (4) says that, for every student, there are philosophy books that the student read (narrow scope), not that there are philosophy books such that every student read those books (wide scope); there is no reading of (4) that requires every student to have read the same books. And (5) says that it’s not the case that there are philosophy books that Sam read (narrow scope), not merely that there are philosophy books that Sam didn’t read (wide scope); there is no reading of (5) on which it’s true even if Sam has read all but two philosophy books ever written.Here is one way to observe this constraint in the context of the resolution. Consider the sentence,

  1. The United States ought to provide military aid to authoritarian regimes and the United States ought not provide military aid to authoritarian regimes.

This sentence expresses a contradiction (or, at least, a hard moral dilemma in which the United States can’t help but do what it shouldn’t). But if “authoritarian regimes” is an existential bare plural that can take wide scope, then (6) should have a reading on which it means that some authoritarian regimes are such that the United States ought to give them military aid and that some (i.e., possibly different) authoritarian regimes are such that the United States ought not give them military aid—which is perfectly consistent, not contradictory. It has no such reading. This shows that, even if existential bare plurals could take wide scope in principle, and even if “authoritarian regimes” is an existential bare plural, it could not take wide scope in the context of the resolution.We can now put the argument together. Affirmatives that restrict their advocacy to particular regimes require a wide-scope existential interpretation of “authoritarian regimes,” as in (3). But, even if such an interpretation were attractive, existential bare plurals can only receive narrow scope. On a narrow-scope existential reading, as in (2), the resolution would say that it shouldn’t be the case that there are authoritarian regimes to which the United States provides military aid—in other words, that the United States should provide military aid to no authoritarian regimes. This interpretation is even stronger than the generic interpretation, and is violated by affirmatives that restrict their advocacy to particular regimes. So regime-specific affirmatives do not even meet the existential interpretation of “authoritarian regimes.”To affirm the resolution, proponents of regime-specific affirmatives must show (i) that the bare plural “authoritarian regimes,” as it occurs in the resolution, has an existential reading, (ii) that existential bare plurals can take wide scope, and (iii) that a wide-scope existential reading of this resolution is at all attractive, despite rendering the resolution obvious and uncontroversial. None of these claims seems to me very plausible, and I think it’s safe to conclude that not all of them are true.But even if they are—even if “authoritarian regimes” can and should take a wide-scope existential reading—I suspect that what many proponents of regime-specific affirmatives really want is for single-regime affirmatives, which advocate that the United States not provide military aid to some one authoritarian regime, to affirm the resolution. Even on a wide-scope existential reading, though, single-regime advocacies do not affirm the resolution because existential bare plurals are still plurals: they require more than one witnessing instance. No matter how wonderful it would be to debate such affirmatives, allowing them is no advantage of the wide-scope existential reading. The resolution simply has no reading on which single-regime advocacies affirm the resolution. You can’t always get what you want.


  1. There’s a Leslie card that is sometimes read as an “I meet” against this violation, and sometimes as a counterinterpretation. This evidence is badly mistagged and misrepresented. The evidence makes the true observation that definite singulars—i.e., singular noun phrases using the definite article “the”—can be used to state generic generalizations (e.g., “The typewriter is obsolete,” or “The woolly mammoth went extinct in the early Holocene era”). This fact is somehow warped to conclude, absurdly, that generics can be affirmed by specifying particular instances. That’s quite a blatant non-sequitur, and indeed Leslie is explicit that generics are generalizations about kinds, not claims about particular members of those kinds.

    To be charitable, I can only speculate that those who don’t take themselves to be misrepresenting the Leslie card are either confused about what definite singulars are or are fallaciously reasoning as follows: (i) as Leslie observes, definite singulars can be used to express generics; so (ii) generics expressed using bare plurals can also be expressed using definite singulars; and (iii) sentences containing definite singulars are entailed by any witnessing instance; so (iv) generics expressed using bare plurals are entailed by any witnessing instance; therefore (v) if the resolution is a bare plural generic, it can be entailed by any witnessing instance. Of course, (i) is true, but (ii) doesn’t follow from (i) and is false: the resolution is a counterexample (try rephrasing it with “the authoritarian regime” without changing its meaning), and more generally Leslie has discussed several interesting differences between bare plural generics and their definite singular counterparts. More importantly, though, (iii) is false—in fact, inconsistent with (ii)—because generic definites are most certainly not entailed by the existence of a single instance; that’s part of what it is for them to be generic. Not even ordinary (nongeneric) definites are entailed by just any witnessing instance, because the definite article presupposes uniqueness: “the F is G” presupposes that there is just one contextually salient F, so on a nongeneric reading there couldn’t be more than one F for the affirmative to choose from. Finally, the falsity of (iv) should be obvious to anyone who has read Leslie’s article or any other introduction to generics that comments on the distinction between generics and existentially quantified statements. But the argument is self-defeating anyway, for if (iv) were true, the inference to (v) would be invalid: (iv) is a generic that would, if true, imply only that some generic (i.e., not necessarily the resolution) can be entailed by a single instance.

    Another widely misused card from Leslie observes that there’s no obvious connection between genericity and frequency, since some generics seem true even though only a small minority of their instances obtain (e.g., “Mosquitos carry malaria”). Some claim that these these “striking property” generics are false overgeneralizations, but suppose we share Leslie’s view on this issue (as I’m inclined to do). What would need to be shown for this to support the counterinterpretation or “I meet” is that (i) the resolution is (or is relevantly like) a striking property generic and that (ii) any striking property generic can be affirmed by a single instance. I know of no reason to believe (i), and (ii) is clearly false; in fact, Leslie insists that genericity is distinct from all of the standard quantifiers, including those—e.g., “at least one”—that can be affirmed by a single instance.

    If you continue to think that these (or any other) cards support an “I meet” or counterinterpretation, please say so in the comments section below and I’ll try to work through them with you.

 

The Case for Orally Disclosing Decisions by Lawrence Zhou

The views and opinions expressed in this article are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of Victory Briefs. Lawrence Zhou was the 2014 NSDA National Champion in LD. He now attends the University of Oklahoma where he is an assistant coach at the Harker School and the Director of Publishing at Victory Briefs.Edit: Thanks to Eva Lamberson for their thoughts and comments. 

Introduction

I imagine that the vast majority of the people who initially read this article are those that will likely already agree with the conclusion that I am about to defend. However, I still believe there is value in writing an article defending a ubiquitous practice in national circuit debate. First, I want people who already agree with the practice of orally disclosing decisions to have something to refer back to when defending this practice to those that may not necessarily agree. Second, I want to directly speak to those who oppose this practice and attempt to have a meaningful dialogue with coaches and tournament directors at local tournaments who prohibit oral disclosure. To that end, this article will primarily be addressed to a skeptical reader. I genuinely want to lay out a case for something I see as a good pedagogical practice and attempt to seriously engage with the criticisms that those who oppose this might levy at it. I hope that, in the spirit of open-mindedness that debate fosters, those who disagree with me will also seriously consider my points and be willing to discuss this in a reasoned manner.The last time I made a post about a traditional tournament, it received substantial criticism in comment threads which were primarily directed at my “privilege” and “national circuit bias”. These are not without merit. It is very difficult to separate my position as someone involved in national circuit debate with my opinions about how traditional debate could potentially be improved. I want to first lay out a little bit of background to help explain where I’m coming from. I debated for a small high school in Oklahoma called Bartlesville High School. I didn’t travel competitively as a debater with the notable exception of the NSDA National Tournament, I didn’t have private coaches, didn’t qualify to the TOC, didn’t come from a place of “debate privilege”, debated in a state that primarily uses paper ballots, etc. I still have a lot of respect for traditional debate, with the NSDA National Tournament being the only tournament I have not missed in the last 8 years. The thoughts I am about to present are ones that are somewhat clouded by my current position as a coach for a larger school and being employed by a debate camp. But they are also thoughts that I think have merit and shouldn’t be immediately dismissed just because of who I am and where I come from, especially since the origin of my beliefs here came from my time in high school.This article will aim to defend post-round oral disclosure, primarily in the context of Lincoln-Douglas debate but these arguments also apply to Public Forum as well. I will begin by clarifying what post-round oral disclosure is, laying out a case for why I believe tournaments should adopt this practice, attempt to substantively engage common objections to this practice, and conclude with a brief call to action on the part of the readers.

What is post-round oral disclosure?

Post-round oral disclosure is when judges will tell the debaters immediately following the conclusion of a debate round at least who won the debate and a brief rationale for their decision. Judges may also, at their own discretion, also provide a few constructive comments to each debater, and, if time permits, answer one or two questions from each debater about how each debater could improve in the future. Post-round oral disclosure, henceforth referred to as PROD, is currently not the norm in many debate circuits around the nation. The current model is one where debaters do not find out until some later time who won the round and do not receive constructive feedback from the judge until after the tournament, typically in the form of a hand-written ballot. I call this post-tournament disclosure. I hope that local tournaments around the country will begin to institute PROD in all varsity and open divisions of Lincoln-Douglas debate. To clarify, I do not think that there should be PROD in junior varsity or novice divisions, and I will address why I believe this to be the case below. I also think there should be a mandatory time limit on the length of oral decisions to be no longer than 5-10 minutes. There are many valid criticisms of this practice but I will first outline my reasoning in defense of PROD and then attempt to address this.

The Case for Post Round Oral Disclosure

I believe there at least three strong pedagogical reasons to support PROD. I will point out what I perceive to be shortcomings in the current model of post-tournament disclosure and explain how I think PROD will help overcome these shortcomings. I will also attempt to alleviate some concerns skeptics might have with each of these particular points within the argument itself.

Immediate Feedback

The current model of post-tournament disclosure only reveals information about how to improve after the tournament has concluded. I believe this is detrimental to the education and growth of debaters for at least two reasons. First, it denies debaters the opportunity to improve during the course of the tournament. Say debaters are making an argument that many judges do not find persuasive (which happens quite frequently). It seems odd to me to think that it is educational experience to allow debaters to not learn from their mistakes over the course of the tournament and not be given the opportunity to improve or correct their mistakes. Second, the details of any particular round will become fuzzy after the tournament ends and the various rounds blur together. Trying to piece any given piece of advice from a judge with a particular in-round practice is quite the puzzle and leads to advice being substantially less effective at helping debaters improve. PROD helps correct this. They now hear feedback immediately following the round. This allows them to understand mistakes they have made early on and gives the opportunity to implement changes to their debating to allow them to improve as the tournament continues. Each and every round is a valuable opportunity to learn something and some of the best learning comes from debating at a tournament. Using each round as an opportunity to improve substantially improves the educational benefit of a tournament. Debating each preliminary round while making the exact same mistake costs debaters that many rounds to improve. This also allows debaters to more clearly understand feedback because the round will have just occurred and the details will still be fresh in their mind. Waiting until after a tournament makes feedback more unclear. This is especially important for tournaments at the end of the season, end of the topic, or important tournaments like one’s state or regional tournament since the feedback given at the end of a tournament becomes much less useful.A skeptic may think I am conflating the role of a debate round. A debate round merely assesses who did the better debating and we shouldn’t think of judges as being primarily interested in educating the debaters. I think this view cannot be squared with the reason why debate is valuable. Debate rounds are useful because they help improve kids. No one can really believe in the value of debate and think that debate rounds at tournaments are not one of the most important parts of the educational experience. Each round is an opportunity for improvement and growth. If we didn’t think that, then why have ballots with sections for judge comments? I think that debate rounds are incredibly important for helping students learn and PROD helps encourage that.

Direct Interaction

The current model of of post-tournament disclosure makes it difficult to determine what the judge means when they write on the ballot. There are many reasons for this: sometimes the handwriting is impossible to read, sometimes tournaments photocopy paper ballots that make them unreadable, time-pressured judges might make a mistake when writing down their comments, or sometimes judges write incomplete or difficult to understand thoughts. None of these are necessarily the fault of the judge, but they do ultimately impair the ability of debaters to learn from their debate rounds. I know that as a debater I was frustrated with paper ballots that contained very little actionable advice because of one of the reasons presented above. This strongly hindered my ability to learn from my debate rounds, see what I needed to improve on, and see what I was doing well that I needed to continue doing. The current model of handwritten ballots results in ballots that aren’t listened to or even seriously considered because of gaps in communication that result when judges cannot accurately translate their thoughts into short handwritten snippets on a ballot. PROD helps address this shortcoming by fostering direct interaction between the debaters and the judge. Judges are now able to quickly explain their decision and then provide actionable feedback in a way that overcomes the confusion of handwritten ballots. This direct interaction, particularly the ability of debaters to ask questions after the round, would clarify confusions and ambiguous thoughts. It would make sure that advice isn’t lost in translation and that confusing parts can be explained. Some of the best advice I ever received in Oklahoma would come from finding the judge after the round and asking them some thoughts about how they thought about a particular argument or how they thought I could improve. I think having a system where this is the norm and not reliant on being friends with a judge is one that would help make post-round feedback more clear and helpful.

Better Judging

Currently, there are too many judges that don’t pay attention in rounds and simply write statements like “aff wins a contention”, “neg was more persuasive”, or “good debate, I vote aff” on their ballots. This, in my mind, is not particularly beneficial or educational for debaters. PROD helps increase judging quality because judges have to immediately disclose their decisions instead of hiding the lack of a complete reason for decision on the ballot. This incentivizes judges to pay attention during rounds and make justifiable decisions to the debaters. This is especially true because debaters now have the opportunity to ask a question or two after the decision is announced which forces judges to consider the implications of their decisions. This also will, in turn, improve the quality of debating. Immediate feedback may also protect the activity’s and judge’s legitimacy, as without an immediate and justifiable reason for decision, debaters can blame a loss on a judge’s personal biases or judge’s lack of knowledge about debate instead of the debater’s failure to persuade the judge.This is perhaps one of the more contentious reasons in support of PROD and I can see many people seeing this as a strong downside to this practice. There are at least two major concerns with this point.First, what about parent judges? After all, it seems at least a little strange to require parents who don’t have a particularly strong grasp of this activity to render oral decisions to debaters. This is a valid concern, but one I think isn’t unique to PROD. If we don’t trust parents to render oral decisions, then why should we trust them to write down comments on paper ballots? Why should we allow them to judge at all? I believe there is a strong value in having parents judge rounds. They make sure debaters stay grounded in the real world and work on their persuasion skills. If we trust parents to make decisions at all, we should trust them to give some oral feedback. I would also wager that most parents are worse at writing down feedback as opposed to giving them aloud. I know that my parents would have difficulty writing down an evaluation of any of the presidential debates, but I know that immediately following the debates, they had verbal comments for both candidates. Parents, or non-debate affiliated judges, actually have a lot of experience in giving their opinions about debates orally but less writing them down. It seems much more consistent with the real world to have parents give their immediate feedback in a way that feels natural to them as opposed to making them write down complicated thoughts on a paper ballot.Second, doesn’t this deter judges from giving feedback if they feel like they don’t know what is going on? Perhaps, but once again, not unique to PROD. Judges will sometimes feel weird judging debates they don’t feel like they can follow. I don’t think is a strong reason to reject the practice. If they feel comfortable writing very little on the ballot, they should feel comfortable saying very little aloud. There's only a chance that at least this practice will encourage judges to think about their decisions more.

Objections

Of course, one may believe the reasons I have set forth in defense of PROD but still oppose the practice for a variety of reasons. I hope to alleviate those concerns.

Objection One: Disclosure takes too much time, delaying the tournament.

This argument has merit, and is probably the strongest objection PROD faces, but an increased turnover time between rounds is, at best, a speculative consequence. The inherent end that debate strives for is to impart a unique form of education, where students are taught to advocate for contrasting positions. While logistics are an obvious side-constraint on any tournament practice, it seems like rejecting PROD (or at least not doing a ‘trial run’ of post-round disclosure at a tournament this year in order to attempt to verify these concerns) for reasons that have not been empirically verified is unjustified when it does not run the risk of undermining the purpose of debate. Maximizing the quality of the educational experience, even if it creates a (small) logistical hurdle for tournaments, should drive tournament officials to make other parts of the tournament more efficient, in order to avoid compromising on the quality of education that the activity provides..Upon further investigation, the ‘time delay’ objection does not hold up to much scrutiny. Proponents of the ‘time delay’ objection cite CX/policy debate as an empirical example of increased turnover time between rounds. While I can’t speak to all tournaments across the country, I can attempt to draw on some examples from the local Oklahoma district I live in. At West Oklahoma debate tournaments, it was actually Public Forum debate that tended to lag behind the rest of the other debate events and cause tournament delays, a debate event without PROD. West Oklahoma also does policy debate at local tournaments. These rounds are magnitudes of order more complex than the average Lincoln-Douglas debate round for a litany of reasons: double the speech time, double the participants, and complex (and perhaps absurd) arguments that require more time to unpack. It also has norms such as flashing documents and PROD that add turnover time. Yet, these rounds also do not substantially turnover time. One could also look to larger invitational tournaments around in the country in Lincoln-Douglas debate. These tournaments all have PROD and these tournaments don’t seem to suffer from extreme turnover time.Finally, PROD trades off with time spent writing up a ballot. In Oklahoma, it seems like a common occurrence that one judge in the pool will delay every round by writing out a detailed ballot. Delivering an RFD orally takes much less time than transcribing complex thoughts onto paper in a legible fashion. In fact, it seems like PROD could potentially speed up time. Judges frequently turn in long, detailed written ballots that delay tournaments because they want to impart a lot of advice to debaters. With PROD, judges can give more advice in less time which could actually speed up tournaments.

Objection Two: Debaters don’t listen to RFDs after being told who won and who lost.

This is also a reasonable concern and one that my former high school debate coach thought was a very serious objection to this practice. It’s not without merit. Anyone who has worked with high school debaters know they have a listening and an ego problem. Why give feedback to them orally if they’re just not going to listen after the decision is announced?Well I believe there are two reasons that this objection is not as serious as it might first appear.First, this is not a phenomenon unique to PROD or even exacerbated by this practice. In the current model, debaters are just going to see ballots after the tournament and just look at if they won or not. If they won, they might not read the ballot because they think they already did so well. If they lost, they might be too angry to read the advice. There is just nothing in the current model that that requires debaters to learn from ballots or even anything that incentivizes them to pay attention the ballot at all. However, PROD forces debaters to sit there and listen. They can’t escape the comments. They may tune out, but they are forced to listen to the judge to some degree so it seems like PROD still increases education. Maybe paper ballots do encourage debaters to listen more because coaches can require debaters to talk about their ballots. But coaches can also require debaters to submit the notes they take over a RFD.Second, this seems almost entirely a problem with debaters, not PROD. If debaters choose not to listen to advice, then they will miss out on the benefits of PROD. Nothing about PROD encourages debaters to tune out, but I imagine most debaters will at least listen to the decisions because they can’t leave and are interested in how to improve so they can win more rounds.

Objection Three: Judges don’t write on ballots if we utilize PROD which means coaches can’t receive proper feedback.

Also a serious concern. Debaters are notorious for filtering all comments through their own biases and so when their coach asks about the judge’s comments, the debater is likely not to accurately describe to the coach what the judge’s comments actually were. This is important and requires careful attention to make sure this problem is adequately addressed.First, I want to point out that this isn’t unique to PROD. Because written ballots are already terrible, parents frequently leave ballots empty, and some tournaments are bad about returning ballots, it is already going to be the case that coaches will not receive much useful information from paper ballots. I can say that when I was doing a little work for local schools, paper ballots provided very little useful information to me as a coach. I wasn’t in the round, I don’t know the judge, and I can very rarely decipher the actual meaning of the ballot anyways. The current model isn’t very useful to coaches as it stands. However, at least some explanation of a decision is required in PROD and debaters will be able to write down some notes about the decision and tell them to their coach, so I believe it probably still is net better for education in this model.Second, there is no reason why there is a strong trade-off because judges can obviously write ballots and give oral feedback. In fact, many judges around the country give both oral and written feedback. Granted, the written feedback will be shorter and less developed. But think of the ballot as a set of bullet points which are then elaborated upon by the oral comments given. This still allows coaches to see the general idea of the comments without the confusion.Third, debaters should obviously be taking notes during the decision either on paper or on their laptop which they can send to their coaches. We expect varsity debaters to help novices, organize preparation, be responsible at tournaments, etc. I think it is reasonable to expect them to also take notices about the round in a responsible manner.

Objection Four: Debaters will argue with the judge.

The threat of debaters arguing with judges is an important one to address, because it has an obvious remedy. When new dimensions are added to debate rounds (such as PROD), new etiquette must be established. There is no reason why ‘do not argue with the judge’ should not be one of the ‘rules of debate’ that coaches teach in their novice debate classes. We were taught to shake our opponent’s hand, thank the judge at the end of the round (but not shake their hand!), and to maintain a polite attitude towards our opponents. I think it reasonable to expect debaters to not argue with the judge. Besides, any self-respecting judge, particularly an adult, will quickly shut down this behavior or just leave the room. The mere possibility of bad conduct on the part of students shouldn’t be a reason to exclude a practice. We expect students to cite their evidence in an academically honest manner even when we don’t check on them, I think we can also expect debaters to know how to be respectful. If they aren’t respectful, then their coaches can reprimand them. The potential for abuse shouldn’t shut down a valuable tool for many other debaters.Proponents of the ‘arguing students’ objection will claim that judges may be deterred to vote for rude debaters in the future, making the debate round unfair. This argument shows that there is a clear incentive for debaters not to argue with judges, and for coaches to teach debaters not to argue with judges. If debaters are punished for arguing with judges, good competitors will not argue with judges, and the issue will resolve itself. Additionally, debaters will argue with judges anyways. They might find them at later tournaments and ask them about decisions in a hostile manner, so PROD doesn’t seem to increase the likelihood of arguing with judges to any significant degree.

Objection Five: PROD is not good for novices.

As I mentioned above, I agree with this. Oral disclosure should not exist in novice divisions. Novices should not be expected to take notes during a decision or understand what is being said. This is not a reason to prohibit PROD in varsity/open divisions. For states that lack distinct varsity and novice pools, I imagine this might pose a potential problem to its implementation, but if the norm is already to expect novices to debate those with many more years of debate experience, I imagine that implementing PROD in those combined divisions would still be a good idea.

Objection Six: Knowing one’s (losing) record discourages debaters from trying their best.

Thanks to Eva for explicitly acknowledging this objection. I have heard this objection before from at least one or two coaches. I doubt this is, by itself, a knockdown objection to the practice, but certainly another reason to have some skepticism about it. I think there are at least two responses that can be made to this.First, it seems that debaters knowing their record is actually somewhat non-unique. The current model privileges debaters who know their judges, have more judges in the pool, more social connections, etc. because they get feedback from the judges but others don’t, including round results. Debaters with coaches in the tab room tend to have more access to information than others, for example, they will often know their preliminary round records before other debaters or have judges that they know give them additional feedback after the round that other debaters don’t receive. This is a very common practice at local tournaments, and seems unfair. While my high school worked in the tabroom and refused, out of principle, to tell us preliminary round records before they were released, there would always be at least a few debaters in the pool that did know their records thanks to connections they had. The PROD model would allow all debaters to receive access to their round records and in-depth commentary and round feedback in an equal manner that the current model does not allow. So I actually believe there is a problem with information asymmetry now and that PROD can correct that. I imagine this is particularly important for schools that lack such strong connections to information sources at tournaments.Second, I just don’t think PROD will exacerbate this problem anymore than the current system. Let’s say my above point is incorrect and that no student has any access to information beyond what the tournament tells them. I still think this problem of students being disincentivized in later rounds exists now regardless of whether or not we acknowledge it. Any semi-competent debater usually has some decent idea of how well they’re doing at a tournament, especially at the margins, which is where this objection is directed. It’s usually not that difficult to guess if you’re 0-3 going into the last round. If that’s the case, these students are already going to get discouraged and not debate their best. I also just don’t see any significant number of debaters who just give up at tournaments where PROD is the norm. Debaters going into their last rounds with losing records are usually still incentivized to win, to not lose that badly, or to have a fun or educational experience in round. While some debaters in the PROD model do not try their hardest when they know they’re losing, my guess is that those are the same debaters who wouldn’t try their best in a world of not disclosing decisions. Finally, even if we believed this objection to be totally true and found it a good reason to not disclose decisions, I still think the practice of at least giving oral feedback and comments would still be beneficial.

Call to Action

I think that PROD is definitely a good norm. It fosters increased accountability of judges and improves the educational experience of debaters. I think that tournaments across the country should adopt this norm and I think there are a few ways to make this more likely to happen.First, individual judges should orally disclose in rounds. This benefits the individual students in the round and sets a precedent for PROD. The more judges that utilize PROD encourages others to adopt PROD as well. Some tournaments may forbid this. I have personally deviated from this rule many times because I believe it is valuable. Even if I don’t disclose who won, I will give comments. I also make sure to keep comments to a reasonable length in time and also write comments on the ballots. Make sure that you are being respectful while promoting this norm. You don’t want people to hate you for doing what you think is right.Second, individual debaters should begin asking, very politely, for judges to orally disclose after rounds. It will encourage judges to think more about PROD and hopefully would make the transition to PROD smoother. It’s important to not force PROD upon anyone, because that would be disrespectful and cause backlash, hampering the long-term adoption of PROD. But there is nothing wrong with asking “do you have feedback for us on how we could improve?” A judge can, of course, say no, and the debater should respect their wishes, but asking can’t hurt.Finally, you can petition coaches and tournament administrators to move towards encouraging oral disclosure in round. The more pressure that exists, the more likely this will be adopted.People didn’t start using Tabroom as a tournament tool until very recently, but slowly, it is becoming a more popular site to host tournaments, mostly because a few schools started using it and began encouraging others to do so as well. PROD is, in my mind, just like Tabroom: a good thing for debate that faces resistance from the more traditional enclaves of debate. I certainly understand the concerns for adopting PROD, but I think that the adoption of PROD would be a net good for debate.

Theis T(h)ursday: Changing Affirmative Speech Times

As you may know, the NSDA is currently considering a number of rule changes for Public Forum. The proposals include changing evidence rules, eliminating cross-fire, and adding time to speeches. Regardless of the merits of any of these specific changes, I think the Lincoln-Douglas community can learn from Public Forum and begin to re-examine our rules.

The Importance of Being Inclusive by David McKay

David McKayDirector, Voices Foundation My son John was passionate about high school debate, feeling it was (in his words) “the most valuable activity a high school student can partake in”.  During his freshman year at college, he became chagrined with what he saw as “…[financial] barriers preventing individuals from fully actualizing their desire to participate in the activity that I owe everything to”, so he took the money he earned from debate coaching and established the Voices Foundation, with the aspiration that “…this organization will have the capability to sponsor and support the individuals who truly wish, but are economically powerless, to maximize their participation in debate”.    At the time, there was tremendous enthusiasm for the organization and its vision.Unfortunately, John died tragically at the age of 19.  Although initially there were efforts from others within the debate community to carry the Foundation forward, for various reasons they floundered.  Although my personal experience in debate had been limited to judging as a parent at tournaments, I agreed to take responsibility for Voices and to try to move it forward.  Several other individuals pitched in and helped.  Our primary initiative to date has been providing financial assistance to needy students wanting to attend summer speech and debate camps.  Over the past 12 years, we have awarded approximately 450 scholarships.It is within that context that I am sharing my perspective as somewhat of an “outsider”—I am not actively engaged in the esoteric strategies and nuances of debating or coaching and winning rounds.  My view is that of a parent and educator who is sincerely concerned about giving young people the opportunity to build positive, productive lives.To be candid, I will admit that initially there was a question in the back of my mind whether a foundation to support high school debate was really needed.  After reading hundreds of personal stories from students and parents over the past 12 years, any trace of a doubt as to whether it is needed has long since vanished.  Voices has supported students from single parent households, including single-disabled-parent or single-disabled-grandparent households that had only a monthly disability check for support; students from families devastated with the financial and emotional burdens of major medical problems, in some cases requiring a parent who would otherwise be employed to serve as a full-time stay-at-home caregiver; children of immigrant families whose parents have only limited, low-paying options for income; a homeless student who was without family and completely on his/her own [gender left unspecified to maintain confidentiality]; a student who, after Voices provided full tuition for a commuter camp, still needed help from social services because he/she didn’t have a couple dollars a day for camp lunch—the list goes on and is very long.  The majority of students that Voices has supported come from families with incomes below the poverty line.  Many qualify for free or reduced lunch at school; many need to work part-time, minimum-wage jobs just to be able to participate in debate.What emerges is a picture of a substantial number of young people living in difficult to desperate circumstances who see education as the route to pull themselves and their families out of poverty, and who aspire to participate in speech and debate as part of that journey.  I think it is critical that we provide them with the opportunities they need and deserve, particularly when one considers what limited options are left for them in absence of such opportunities.But what can be done?  Clearly, money is a limiting factor.  What Voices and similar foundations have been able to accomplish is barely a drop in the bucket, when compared to the overall need.  But will more money, by itself, solve the problem?  In asking how to move forward, it may be instructive to look back at how Voices got to where it is.When John decided to found Voices, he didn’t ask for advice or permission; he enlisted his debate buddies and took the initiative to move the idea forward.  Frankly, he had an attitude that “old people”--which seemed to include most people over the age of 25 at that point--talked a lot but did little.  Although technically, some of the things he did were not correct (as the IRS explained to him at one point), arguably he did things right—he was able to marshal enthusiastic support within the community for an initiative to break down the financial barriers that thwarted many from participating.  The key factor was not money, it was an individual deciding to make something happen.  Without his efforts, the 450 scholarships that Voices has awarded over the past 12 years would not have happened.   I sincerely hope that students in the community will take this lesson, and a bit of his attitude, to heart.Finally, I would like to comment, again as an outsider, on measures of success in debate.  Most often, students measure their success by where they stand in the win-loss column relative to other debaters.  Debate is a highly competitive activity, and this is certainly a measure that is heavily emphasized, along with TOC bid lists, etc.However, I would argue there is a second measure, which is where students stand in their ability to objectively research topics in depth and clearly articulate arguments and counterarguments, relative to where they would be if they didn’t participate in debate. I would argue that in the long run, this second measure is more important than the first. Did Martin Luther King or John F. Kennedy every win a speech or debate tournament?  I have no idea.  Were they able to inspire people and influence the course of history with their ability to clearly articulate a vision?  Absolutely.  Students will utilize the fundamental skills that they develop by participating in speech and debate long after win-loss records have faded.  In this context, the long-term value of the community proactively reaching out to be inclusive of the financially disadvantaged cannot be overstated.To contact the Voices foundation, please email them at: admin@voicesfoundation.org.

Preparing for the Season: An Interview with Sekou Cisse

Check out our interview with VBI staffer Sekou Cisse.Sekou debated for Success Academy HS in NY and had 9 career TOC bids, winning the Byram Hills Invitational + RR, the Beltway fall classic, the Newark RR, the Berkeley RR, NYC Policy RR, Kandi King RR, the Harrison RR, and Harvard. Sekou currently attends and debates for Wake Forest University. He was an instructor at VBI 2018.In this interview, we discuss how to approach preparing for tournaments, the key to success, and how he won Harvard, among other subjects.https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=WpVWYA12hSI

Preparing for Nationals: An Interview with a National Champion

With NSDA Nationals quickly approaching in just over a week, we thought we’d sit down and ask the most recent NSDA National Champion, Natalie Schaller, about preparing and competing at NSDA Nationals. This continues from an interview we did last year with the 2016 and 2014 NSDA National Champions, which you can find here. Natalie is currently entering her second year at McGill University and won NSDA Nationals in 2017 competing for Liberty Senior High School in Missouri. The following is an edited interview with Natalie. You can find the full, unedited interview at the bottom of this page. (The editors recommend reading the full, unedited interview for those interested in really preparing for NSDA Nationals.)

1. Natalie, you won NSDA Nationals last year in 2017. Tell us a bit more about yourself. What was your best memory from Nationals? How was debating in finals? What did it feel like when you won?

Originally, I’m from Kansas City, Missouri, which I think is a terrific place to grow up. Of course, I really found my home in Liberty High School’s Speech and Debate program. On the team, I competed in LD, OO, and USX for my first year. As a second year, I ended up temporarily switching to Policy for the season. My Policy partner, Stefanie Flood, was (and is) really a one-of-a-kind person. She taught a lesson all debaters must learn: it doesn’t matter if you (or your opponents) have won or lost in the past, what matters is the round right in front of you. This mindset became important as I began a very difficult transition back to LD during my third year. I had a 2-2 record at most tournaments. If I was lucky enough to break, I was usually done by quarterfinals. I never qualified to the State tournament. I felt immensely disappointed and insecure those last two years. But, Stefanie’s lesson still resonated with me. My poor record in the past didn’t have to define my debate future, so I couldn’t give up on myself or the activity I loved so much.I say all of this because by the time 2017 Nationals came around, I was very much aware that all of the work I had put in to training might not do me any good. This was an intimidating reality, and it created a great deal of pressure as the tournament progressed. Somehow, though, I knew that tournament wouldn’t be like the other ones. I had finally internalized everything my terrific coach, Mr. Timothy Baldwin, had said to me for the past four years. It doesn’t matter who your opponent is or where they come from - the only people in the room that matter are you and the judge. Walk into every round knowing you aren’t alone. If you want something, just go out there and get it. Simple as that. I want other debaters to be impacted by those words as much as I was.Even with this positive mindset, Nationals was highly challenging and demanding, and each round was closer than the last. Despite the difficulty, I have such great memories from the tournament. My happiest one was when I was surrounded by my teammates and coach as we prepped on the night before finals. There was something so heartwarming about being surrounded by the people I cared about most, working on the activity I loved the most, all of us helping each other. You really do nothing in this world alone, and it’s awesome to be able to learn from other people. That evening was the most humbling reminder of that. If you’re reading this, you should take some time to reflect on the people you’re happiest to do life with, and then go thank them for being there.The day of finals was probably the most nervous I’ve ever been, and that’s saying something. I was afraid I would buckle under the pressure, so I tried to focus on routine. You prep your binder, get your files ready, listen to some music, relax, then just go out there and do your thing. I told myself I couldn’t do anything differently, and just treat it as another debate round. Keeping up that mentality helped me become focused and relaxed, and then I remember just trying to go out there and have the time of my life. It was the last round I would ever compete in, so I wanted to soak it all up: the cases, the cards, the strategy, the warrants, the rebuttals. I just had fun with it. I also had the distinct pleasure of competing against Nathan Davis, an incredibly sharp and talented debater from the Heart of America district in Missouri. This made the round even more enjoyable, because I knew I had a friend there with me.To answer the last part of the question, winning Nationals did not feel real for a very long time. It still doesn’t, almost a year later. It’s important to me that I say I did not win. Mr. Baldwin, won. Stefanie Flood, won. My team from Liberty High School won. My sister team from Liberty North High School won. The Heart of America District won. Missouri won. I am not a really great debater on my own. The only reason that win happened was because for four years, I was lucky enough to lose to so many brilliant and talented people who molded me into the person, and debater, I eventually became. That’s what makes debate special - it’s all a community effort. I can’t tell you how blessed and lucky I feel to have such fond memories of that community.

2. Nationals is a tournament like no other because of its large pool of debaters and brings in so many judges from across the nation with different perspectives. What advice do you have for those preparing for Nationals in Florida this summer in terms of adapting to so many different judges? In your opinion, what is the most important thing to do in order to make it to outrounds and succeed at NSDA Nationals?

There is no exact science for this, but I recommend reviewing all the judge paradigms you can whenever your judges are released (and do this early - you don’t want to be scrambling five minutes before your first round starts to learn what you’re about to get yourself into). Get a piece of paper, make a section for each round, and take notes on the paradigms of Judge 1, 2, and 3 (and so on, if you’re in outrounds). Figure out the stylistic preferences of the majority of your judges in any given round, and then tailor your approach to the majority. You might not be able to win over one judge, so try for the other two. Of course, this does not mean you should abandon the preferences of your third judge. Still try to incorporate some things they want to see in the round, because otherwise they’ll feel as though you’ve ignored their paradigm sheet. So, strike a balance, but bear in mind the majority when need be.A final note on judge adaptation is that it doesn’t end when you’re done looking at the paradigm sheet. Debate requires you to constantly be alert of the folks in the back of the room. Study their facial expressions and body language as you speak. Are they nodding along and eagerly writing? Do they look alert and focused? Or, are they shaking their head and only writing when your opponent is speaking? Cues like these can help you determine if a judge is buying what you’re selling. If they’re not, try to either win over the ones who are, or adapt your argument in a way that they respond better to.

3. Nationals is also a tournament like no other because it is a week long. For many, this can be really stressful and tiring. What advice do you have for those competing at Nationals in Florida this summer on how to survive Nationals?

A few pieces of advice come to mind here. Of course, caring for your health is important. Don’t goof off - get as much sleep as you can, drink water, don’t go overboard on the coffee, and try to find some healthy meals. What’s more important is staying mentally strong throughout the tournament, because Nationals really is a mental game. I have to admit, I cannot take credit for the advice I’ll give here – they’re all tips that Mr. Baldwin gave me throughout my debate career.First, focus on what you can control. Don’t get caught up in the kids that will loudly talk about their argumentative prowess or their latest debate achievements. People are trying to intimidate each other, but don’t let that get to you. It doesn’t matter where your opponent goes to school, which tournaments they travel to, etc. Use your energy to just think about executing your strategy and playing the game, one round at a time. If you just focus on what you’ll say, all of that background noise fades away, and you’ll find yourself in a really terrific headspace.Second, you have to abandon your fear of failure. I found that I performed worse whenever I psyched myself out before a round while thinking about how epically I might lose. When you acknowledge that you might lose and you prepare yourself to be okay with that, it’s much easier to enter the round and know that there really isn’t any pressure on you. Your only obligation from that point on is to do your best and to trust your training.Third, speaking of trust - you must have an unwavering faith in yourself and your abilities. When you walk into every round, you have to know that there’s no argument that you cannot answer. You have your brain, and that’s really all that you need. Actually believing this creates immense relief at the tournament, because you trust yourself so much that you will not falter when you encounter an argument/case that is unfamiliar.Fourth and finally, walk into every round with the knowledge that you are never alone. I think this is true for everything you may face in life, but it’s especially true in debate. Each time you enter your round, you go in with your coach(es), your teachers, your teammates, your greatest friends - and all of the people who have ever impacted their lives, too. You’ll feel empowered if you remember this, because at any given point in time, you know you’ve got a whole army on your side. They’ll be with you every step of the way.

4. Success at Nationals isn’t just about competing at the tournament itself, but also about preparing for the tournament beforehand. How did you approach preparation before Nationals? Did you spend a lot of time doing drills or practice rounds or did you do something entirely different?

For the first week to week and a half after the topic has been released, do as much research as possible. I think I averaged around six hours a day of just combing through databases and law reviews, attempting to find compelling arguments and case studies. This research needs to be done diligently: you cannot be distracted if you want to absorb and process such a high volume of information so quickly, and you certainly cannot be lazy.I recommend keeping a research journal to keep yours searches focused and fruitful. To start, brainstorm a master list of search terms, adding more as you discover new terms in articles and journals. After you’re done with each term, write down the major arguments and case studies you found, as well as whether or not the term was useful at all. Doing this allows you to keep track of new discoveries, while simultaneously preventing you from searching the same things over and over.After this phase, spend the next week writing cases. This process looks different for everyone, so I really can’t speak to best practices here. I will say, however, that it’s important to keep the big picture of the debate round in mind. Given all of your research, what do you want to be able to say in the 1NR and 2AR? What will the themes of your voting issues be? How will you tell your story? Start from this endpoint and then work backwards (filling your case with the arguments that will get you where you need to go in the rebuttals). Also, keep in mind that you want to hide some impact defense or turns in your case (if it works well with your framework/contentions and won’t sacrifice more important arguments). For example: this can be as simple as adding two or three lines to the end of a contention on your aff that will likely diffuse the neg’s largest impact.The remaining time before Nationals should really be spent on cross-ex prep, answer-to blocks and practice. My advice would be to spend about a week on a master list of answer-to blocks, and then move right in to practice drills and rounds. I genuinely believe that rehearsing delivery made all the difference for me at Nationals. If you’re able to, film yourself doing all of the drills so that you can review your delivery and tailor it as needed (and, of course, practice in front of a coach/teacher/parent). I found a few drills to be especially useful:

  1. Practice rehearsing the major theme of your case. If you had to sum up the aff/neg in thirty seconds, what would it be?

  2. Write down a list of five arguments at a time (either all aff or all neg), and then practice answering them. Just go down the line, one by one. The purpose of this drill is really just to familiarize yourself with answering common warrants and impacts. You can include answering different values/value criterions here, too.

  3. Debate yourself. This sounds a bit crazy, because it is. But I mean - flow both your aff and neg, deliver your aff, sit down and write case answers, stand up and read the 1NC and answer the aff, sit back down and write neg answers and aff case defense, stand up and give the 1AR, and so on. This is the best drill, in my opinion, because you’re debating your best opponent - you! You know all your tricks and winning impacts, so you are forced to answer the arguments you naturally find most threatening.

  4. Debate other people. If you can, try to set up practice rounds with kids from schools nearby (I always found this to be more productive than doing rounds with students on your own team). Have a coach watch these rounds, too, because they can likely help you catch some major argumentative errors you might have been missing.

The last thing I’ll say about practice drills is that they’re not a one-and-done kind of ordeal. You should do them for about three hours at a time on any given day, and you need to do them over and over until you get it right.Finally, in order to go far at Nationals, you have to work harder than you ever have before. You cannot skate by. Be prepared to give it your all and stretch your limits.

5. Any last pieces of advice for those competing at Nationals this year?

You cannot win a national championship if you’re in it for the trophy or for the recognition. In fact, this approach will likely damage your efforts. Your ego will not carry you through when you have hardly eaten or slept in days, you’re down one round, and you’re about to debate some of the most brilliant minds in the country. What will keep you going is heart.In those most difficult moments at the tournament, I remembered everything about my debate career - start to finish. I remembered the first time freshman year that I got goosebumps because I found the perfect argument in my research. I remembered being in a Policy semifinals round during my second year and finally getting the intrinsicness perm argument right. I remembered the pep talks my debate coach would give my team the night before districts, telling us that nobody and no situation could ever take away our hard work from the season. I remembered how my infinitely compassionate and genuine teammate, Lexie Cree, sat in the back of my rooms during outrounds at Nationals so I felt less scared and alone. I mainly remembered that no matter what was happening in my life at any given point in time, debate felt like home, and nothing had ever made me so happy.If you have that love for the activity and you are consumed with how incredible and exciting and empowering it is, you can do anything and win any round. You can overcome any obstacle because you have the heart to do it. If you just remember that feeling and run headfirst into each round, having fun and doing what you love - well, you really can’t ever lose, can you?Special thanks to Natalie for her answers.Download the full interview here: Preparing for Nationals Natalie Answers

Packing For Debate Camp: An Interview with VBI Staffers

One of the most frequently asked questions we get is, “What should I pack for camp?” We were asked this last year on our VBI AMA on Reddit (which you can find here) and we responded with a few different answers.“As for packing, you can find our packing list here. My personal suitcase for camp contains 8 days of clothes, a computer, chargers, headphones, a bluetooth speaker, pens, paper, and spending money. One thing that is often overlooked is the benefit of having sandals or flipflops for when you’re just in your dorm. The good news is we provide linens and towels so you don’t have to worry about packing those! - Lawrence Zhou”“As for packing I would always bring a deck of cards and a few small games (this year I will probably bring bananagrams, avalon, coloretto, anomia, biblios and maybe a larger game like settlers of catan if I can fit it in). I would also recommend bringing a non-debate related book or a kindle. -Marshall Thompson”As camp approaches, it’s worth thinking a little bit more about packing for camp. The following is an edited interview with several VBI staffers and what they pack for camp. They will provide their insights on what and what not to pack to survive and thrive at camp. Hopefully you all will find something interesting in this article and take some inspiration from these seasoned camp veterans.A link to the full, unedited interview can be found at the bottom of this article.

1. Tell us about yourself.

Alex Chin: My name is Alex, and I’m a rising sophomore at Harvard and assistant coach at the Boston Latin School (and sometimes I coach for my high school, Nueva). I’m not really sure what I’m majoring in (still have a semester to decide), but it’ll probably be something along the lines of math, physics, or computer science (possibly a secondary in philosophy). I’m originally from San Francisco, California, and this will be my second year at VBI.Christian Quiroz: My name is Christian Fernando Quiroz, people usually just call me CQ. I’m going into my senior year at Rutgers University-Newark where I am a part of the debate team and the honors living learning community, and major in Philosophy and minor in Social Justice. My field of expertise is continental philosophy with a special interest in Schopenhauer, Dostoevsky, and Nietzsche. I’ve been involved in debate for about 7 years and I’m excited to be returning to VBI for my 4th year teaching!Nick Smith: My name is Nick, I studied Political Science & Philosophy at the University of Minnesota, and I am the head coach at Apple Valley High School. I’ve been involved in debate since 2005 and I am super pumped for my seventh summer of working at VBI!Jami Tanner: I'm Jami! I’m currently studying at NYU, in the BA/MA track for Political Science. I’ve been involved with debate for ten years now (wow I’m old) and will be returning to VBI for my fourth year as the Director of PF!Max Wu: Hi, my name is Max Wu! I’m going into my sophomore year at the University of Chicago, where I plan on majoring in Political Science with a focus on International Security studies. I’m originally from Fremont, California, a Bay Area suburb east of San Francisco. Between coaching and competing, I’ve been involved in the Public Forum debate community for 6 years, and am looking forward to working another summer at VBI.Maya Xia: My name is Maya, and I’m an incoming freshman at Vanderbilt University majoring in Neuroscience. I competed as a Lincoln-Douglas debater for four years in high school, and I’m really excited to return to camp as a first-year LD instructor!Pacy Yan: Hi, I’m Pacy. I’m from New York City, where I attended Stuyvesant High School. I’m a current senior and I debated on the Lincoln-Douglas team for four years. I will be studying at NYU this coming fall and I’m super excited to be teaching at VBI this year!

2. When do you start packing for camp usually?

Christian: I typically try to at least get some of the things I know I’ll need for camp together about a week before. So any clothes I might want to bring or shoes or sandals I put to the side so that I know those are the things I want to bring. I don’t actually start packing until the night before.Max: Under the guise of youthful confidence, I started packing a day before I left for camp last year. This was a very poor decision. In my haste, I neglected to bring a number of important articles to camp, including a belt, toothpaste, and underpants. I also did not have enough time to check weather forecasts in Los Angeles, and packed too many pairs of pants. You can’t wear pants in LA during the summer. It’s illegal.Maya: I usually pack for camp the day before (oops), but the packing is pretty easy since I bring much of the same things that I bring on vacation (i.e. clothes, toiletries, computer) plus flow paper and my laptop stand.Pacy: I usually start about three to four days in advance, mostly because my mom bugs me about it and, even as I’ve grown up and she bugs me way less about it, I’ve just gotten into the habit of doing it. It makes the day before a lot less stressful!

3. What clothes or outfits do you consider essential for camp, and how many days of clothes do you usually bring?

Christian: Sandals sandals sandals. And a lot of socks. The fashion police are always trying to give me a ticket for wearing socks and sandals, but they’re comfy. I also like to bring sweat shorts because, again, they’re really comfy. I usually try to bring about a week and a half worth of clothing. Honestly that has just happened to be what I’ve packed before, I’ve never consciously picked out a certain number of outfits for camp.I try to not pack too much for camp, leaving a little space in my bag, because I always like to shop while I’m away in other places and I always try to account for this. It’s not always clothes, though, I also like to shop for books that would need space in my luggage.Pacy: I bring about seven to ten days worth of clothes/outfits. Beyond absolutely necessary things (socks, undergarments, pants, shirts), more specific and important things to consider is bringing a hoodie or something that is like a jacket. Although camp is during the summer, it can get quite chilly at night. Also, hoodies are super comfortable! For pants, bring something other than just shorts – like leggings or jeans or long pants. Also, dress comfortably! Camp can be tiring and busy sometimes so make sure you are comfortable in what you wear.Nick: Without fail I somehow end up packing some clothing that is too hot to reasonably wear on most summer days. Philadelphia can be super humid, and Los Angeles is almost always quite warm. If you see me drenched in sweat and wearing flannel, then please feel free to have an internal chuckle at my expense. Having like one or two warmer pieces of clothing wouldn’t be the worst idea for times like a cool night in LA. I typically plan on doing laundry once a week, which means I pack ~8 days worth of clothing to play it safe. There will always be access to laundry facilities when you’re staying in the dorms. Other than that, I make sure to pack two pairs of comfortable shoes as there will be a good deal of walking on paved surfaces.Jami: I typically bring enough outfits for 10 days, but end up rotating the same 4 outfits because I have that habit…

4. What are the essentials you can’t live without?

Alex: This is pretty obvious, but make sure to bring your laptop. My first time at debate camp, I didn’t realize I needed a laptop until the day before, and my laptop was broken so I had to make a bunch of runs to the Apple Store the day before—not a good idea. I would also bring paper, pens (if you’re looking for a debate pen, check out the coleto lumio on amazon), and a folder/binder too keep your stuff in.Max: Skincare products, vegan protein powder, noise-cancelling headphones, college apparel, existential dread.Christian: Clothes and toiletries are obvious, I try to bring the travel bags that you can keep your toiletries in so that I don’t have to keep track of my toothbrush, deodorant, etc. when I go to shower I just bring all my things with me so it’s not as hectic.I also always bring my laptop and gaming mouse. I have a razor mouse that has shortcuts on the side to optimize gaming. I also bring my laptop so I can do work and play league of legends. This year I’ll probably be playing more fortnite on my laptop.I also have a pretty decently sized library now, and as much as I’d love to bring all of my books with me, I select a few that I need for summer research/reading, enjoy to read just to read (such as novels), or if I promised to lend it to someone during camp. If you’re interested in a book I might have, let me know and I’ll bring it!Pacy: Beyond hygeine essentials (toothbrush/paste, shampoo, conditioner, deodorant, etc) and clothing, some other really important things for me to bring are my headphones, stuffed animals, potentially a light and soft blanket, hair ties, and slippers. Headphones are important since I like music, also they’re useful when you just want to relax and listen to music. I really love stuffed animals and I often carry them around with me. Blankets are awesome and fluffy! You can wrap it around yourself or someone else. Hair ties are very useful, especially if the weather is warm. Slippers are good for things like communal bathrooms or even the beach (if you’re attending LA1/2)! Also, things like basic medicine (allergy meds, cold medicine, etc) and things like lotion and skincare products are also important! Also, laundry detergent pods are useful.

5. What is something that people always forget to bring to camp?

Nick: A compact umbrella (Swarthmore). Basic hygiene products like DEODORANT, toothbrush, toothpaste, shower supplies, etc. Basic debate supplies like pens, paper, a timer, a flash drive, an organization system, etc. Enough clean clothes to make it through camp or a willingness to do laundry when necessary.Jami: Hmmm… I’m not too sure what kids forget to bring, but I know one thing that they always are prepared with: snacks. Loving parents always send their kids off to camp with an absurd amount of snacks and, every summer, kids frantically are trying to figure out what to do with the 500 granola bars they haven’t finished as they’re getting ready to leave camp. (I’ve also seen a student who was sent with a 2 lb bag of apples!) I think it’s super sweet - definitely something my mom did for me when I went out of town for tournaments.Alex: Remember that you’re going to be living in dorms, so you should bring all the basic toiletries like shampoo, conditioner, soap (a surprisingly high number of people don’t bring soap), et cetera. Also, if you wear contact lenses, don’t forget to bring those easier. I’ve definitely forgotten to bring those at tournaments in the past and it’s really tough.I’d also bring a water bottle—it’ll just be more convenient that way.Pacy: People will sometimes forget chargers for things like laptops (which everyone should bring! Don’t forget your laptop!), phones, etc. That would become super inconvenient and you would either have to buy another one or borrow someone else’s for a few weeks. Also, bring money since you will potentially order food or buy things at camp (especially if you forget essentials!). Also, don’t forget to bring enough socks or clothes in general – it would be weird if you wore the same shirt every other day. Also, if you can, bring a timer! Those are super useful for debate camp.

6. What are things you like to bring to camp to make life more fun?

Maya: I’m not a huge gamer, so there’s not a material possession that made camp more fun for me. I definitely recommend bringing your personality and an open mind because the people you meet at camp are pretty amazing. I met some of my closest debate friends at camp. Although we competed in different areas around the nation, I still kept in contact with them throughout the school year, and being able to hang out with a few them at tournaments made the competitive atmosphere a lot more enjoyable and less daunting since I had a group of friends there to support me.Alex: I would recommend bringing some snacks—granola bars or popcorn or whatever your snack of preference is. There aren’t really TVs or anything to plug consoles into, so don’t bother bringing them. I’ve enjoyed playing cards and Frisbees (or a football or soccer ball, etc.) at camp.Nick:  I’m VERY excited to be bringing my Nintendo Switch to camp this summer. I’m going to annihilate Lawrence in Mario Kart!! I’ll probably bring a low-key game or two that I can play in the small random periods of downtime I have at camp.My Kindle always follows me to camp, which loaded with oodles of books that are on my reading list. I suspect that I might get more reading done if I simply brought a few paperbacks instead; decision fatigue is real. Most of these books are books that I want to read for fun and not books that might somehow be useful for debate so that I can unwind easier.My general advice on this subject would be to bring the things that you can see yourself having fun using with other folks. Things like a deck of cards, some card games (shout-outs to Total Rickall, a Rick & Morty card game), coloring books, a hacky sack, snacks to share (keeping in mind common allergies), or whatever floats your boat. I always say that the people are the best part of being involved in and camp is a wonderful opportunity to meet and form lifelong friendships with some cool new folks.Jami:  A deck of cards!!! Nothing fancy. There are so many card games for multiple players, and it’s really such a good way to spend time with people you’ve just met. If you want to get really fancy, get Avalon. The best game ever, especially when you’re playing with a bunch of debaters. I played with staff and students almost every night last summer, and I even bought my own game for myself at home.

Conclusion

We hope you found this interview helpful, insightful, or interesting. There are many things to consider when packing for camp, and this hopefully gave you some inspiration and ideas for when you pack for camp!Download the full, unedited interview here: All Packing Interview Answers

How to Prep for Tournaments: Before, During, and After By Raffi Piliero

Raffi Piliero debated for Harrison High School for 4 years, clearing at the TOC twice, and finishing as bid leader his senior year. He also won several national tournaments and several top speaker awards, and now debates for Georgetown University.

Introduction:

Previously, I’d written an article about what to do to get ready or the season to start during the off-season. This article will instead focus on what to do during the season to get ready for tournaments. Specifically, we’ll go over optimal ways to do in the weeks leading up to that next big tournament, the day before, during the tournament, and recovering successfully from a draining weekend.

Before:

This section will examine both what you should do in the short term before a tournament (i.e., the night before, the morning of) but also in the more medium to long term before a tournament, in terms of how to prioritize what prep to do.

  1. Set goals. This can help both motivate you before the tournament, but also create good benchmarks to see improvement. My coach, Mr. Hertzig, always used to have me create an index card the week before a tournament where I’d put 3 goals for the tournament, and then 3 specific actions to get there (e.g., I’ll do 4 practice rounds, 5 1AR redoes, etc.)
  2. Go through the NDCA Wiki and make sure you’re set on every major broken position. This sounds intuitive and obvious, but a surprising number of debaters seem to walk into tournaments without a very sophisticated understanding of positions that have been read previously, and are caught off guard when seeing them or the first time pre-round. I’d suggest making some kind of Google Doc that includes both what the major AFF and NEG positions are for anyone entered in the tournament, as well as a constantly updated list of things that need to be cut to ensure nothing slips through the cracks.
  3. On a related note to the above, having specific case negs/strats to the most threatening positions and debaters is also helpful. While it likely wouldn’t be worth the time (or possible) to compile extensive files to everyone in the pool, you should have extensive files for the most common positions, and specific evidence/scripting against positions you’re most worried about. This helps take some of the pressure off pre-round, and helps avoids that moment of terror when you realize you’re Neg against an Aff that you really don’t have a good strat against.
  4. Be familiar with your prep – this is a super simple and easy thing for most people to alter that has a substantial impact on both knowing what prep to do and being able to explain arguments in round. You should be able to delve into what your evidence says beyond just what the tag (or even the highlighted components say) and be able to talk intelligently about an argument. One additional suggestion is to highlight all of your own cards – this is something that happens in college debate much more frequently than in high school, but I’m all for it – while a bit more time consuming, it ensures greater familiarity with the evidence set you’re likely to be reading.
  5. Be ready for new positions to be broken. The best debaters are proactive, and not just reactive. You should have a set of generic positions (process/agent CPs, DAs that link to most Affs such as politics or federalism, NCs, Ks, etc.) that you can pull from if someone breaks a totally new Aff. This is especially true leading up to major tournaments where people have had months to prep and find new angles on the topic. Additionally, it’s also good to have tricks up your sleeve and new things to say even if they read something new! For example, leading up to TOC, I encouraged the kids that I coach to read some new CPs that nobody had read on the topic, and some tricky new politics DAs if the situation called for it with a new Aff – this was intended to ensure that the Aff could be equally caught off guard.
  6. Do speeches and drills. Daily speaking drills are definitely important to ensure that you maintain clarity and build speed as time goes on in the season, but additional speeches/practice debates can also be helpful. Whether redoing a speech from a round you lost earlier in the season or just practicing a 2NR on an unfamiliar Neg position vs a strange Aff, practice is essential. Ideally, you’re never taking a totally new strategy for a trial run in an actual debate but have practiced it beforehand in front of coaches or teammates. Similarly, doing practice debates with teammates or friends, with someone giving feedback is extremely useful. This gives the perfect opportunity to try out new strategies without the pressure of a tournament, and a great chance to hone weaknesses. As the great Marshall Thompson once told me, “If you’re winning practice rounds, then you’re doing something wrong”; trying new things that you’re bad at ultimately should be the goal to improve.
  7. Strike a good balance between prep and drills. Both are important, but there’s a point in there can be too much of a good thing. It’s probably not worth it to redo that 1AR an extra 10 times if looking at your files, you realize you still don’t have full 1NC to the biggest Aff of the topic. Similarly, there’s a point of diminishing marginal returns to making 10 case negs to 10 iterations of the most common Aff when you could be doing a set of practice debates in that same timeframe.
  8. Stay healthy. This is probably the suggestion that people will brush off, but it’s far and away the most important, especially in the day or so leading up to the tournament. Eat healthy and get sleep in the week before the tournament – tournaments have incredibly nutrient-deficient food and sleep is sometimes hard to come by, which makes it all too easy to get sick during a tournament. As much as we all pretend debate is a sport, it’s not, and exercise is good/healthy, too!

During:

This section will focus on what to do from when you arrive at the tournament to the moment you leave, and how to maximize your time there.

  1. Warm up. Nobody is going to sound their best at 7AM in the morning, and the best way to counteract that is to do speaking drills when you warm up. By this I don’t mean sloppily reading through a couple of cards and calling it a day; you should probably spend 20-30 minutes making sure that you sound as good as possible to get off to a good start early on.
  2. Stay on top of what’s happening with new prep. Unfortunately, you’re probably not the only person who thought to cut a sweet new Aff before the tournament, and when other people are reading new prep, you’ll want to know. Check the NDCA Wiki constantly during the tournament, and stay on top of what people are reading.
  3. Be productive in between rounds. While waiting for the pairings, it’s good (and important) to decompress from the last round, but you should also aim to be productive, either in terms of getting prep done to any new positions or just making sure your existing files are good to go.
  4. Get ready effectively for each round. When the pairing comes out, the first thing to do is to figure out the Aff if you’re neg, or past 2NRs if you’re Aff. Then, the rest of the time before the round should be spent pulling the necessary cards, cutting any that seem missing, and writing blocks/extensions/scripting for rebuttals to save time in round and to make arguments as powerfully worded as possible.
  5. Use decision time effectively. After the 2AR ends, you could have upwards of 15-20 minutes (or longer) to do the aforementioned checking of the Wiki, write blocks, or, in an elim, prepare for the next debate.
  6. Stay healthy. This is just as important as it was in the above section. Don’t forget to eat meals, stay hydrated, and get to sleep at a reasonable hour. There’s no card that could be cut at 1AM that’s worth not just cutting in the morning – trying to get around 8-9 hours is really, really important in terms of being able to execute well the next day.

After:

Once you’ve left the tournament, what next?

  1. Catch up on life. Whether this means making sure any homework is done, eating a good meal for the first time in days, or just sleeping, do it.
  2. Think about what went right and what went wrong. Did you meet goals that you’d set out for the weekend? Did you give any especially good speeches, or any especially poor ones? This can help you orient how you approach the next tournament.

Hope this helps! Best of luck!

Negative Strategy – How to Make the 1AR a Nightmare by Raffi Piliero

Raffi Piliero debated for Harrison High School for 4 years, clearing at the TOC twice, and finishing as bid leader his senior year. He also won several national tournaments and several top speaker awards, and now debates for Georgetown University.

Introduction:

One of the first things that even the youngest of debaters realize upon giving a 1AR is how challenging it is. 4 minutes to respond to 7 minutes in the NC, and the potential for a 6-minute collapse to whatever was most lightly covered make answering everything sufficiently a real challenge. The best debaters know how to set up a 2NR that’s both well crafted, and takes advantage of significant 1AR missteps. We all know the 1AR is hard, but this article will go over some ways to make the 1AR even harder than ever!

1. Know when to layer

One of the fun things about being neg is that while the AFF speaks first and sets the round, the NC gives plenty of wiggle room to put out lots of different sources of offense, giving the 2NR a plethora of choices from which to pick. From CPs to DAs to Ks to T violations to NCs, the options seem endlessThere’s no one rule of thumb for how many layers are too many, and how many are too few. Plenty of successful neg debaters made it a habit to read 3 off case positions and answer the case; others 2, some even 4. For the most part, the number of layers should depend on several factors. These include, but aren’t limited to, the quality of both your case arguments and off case arguments (if the link turn is true and your cards are great on it, why not heavily invest in that and cut down on the number of time spent reading other, inferior layers?), the judge, and concerns about 1AR theory.Successful layering involves having diversified offense. For example, an NC that relies on the same fundamental premise as several case turns allows the Aff to just beat one argument, and the rest all go away. Similarly, there’s no point in reading two DAs with an econ impact, since then arguments on one page apply to the other as well.It’s often useful to also have different types of arguments as well; what I mean by this is arguments that challenge different components of the Aff and interact with Aff offense in different ways. For example, reading a DA and a framework NC might be more strategic than reading two Das if it seems like the framework isn’t particularly well justified; then, if after the 1AR, it seems like the Aff is ahead on substance, the 2NR can make a choice to mitigate that by just going for the NC. Leaving the 2NR plenty of options and forcing the 1AR to debate the framework, and substance is a good way to force the Aff to not make mistakes However, this isn’t to say that doubling down early in the debate is always a mistake. For example, if the Aff expects a framework-heavy strategy and frontloads a ton of framework preempts in the 1AC, going for 2 DAs and a CP might be something that throws them off guard, and moots most of the 1AC.In line with this, it’s often important and helpful to think of neg arguments in terms of time tradeoff. Given 1AR time pressures, if an argument takes you an equal time to make as it does for the 1AR to deal with it sufficiently, that’s a great time tradeoff since it likely means the 1AR had to undercover something as a result. In contrast, if an argument took you a minute to make but the 1AR dismisses it in 30 seconds, then that’s a much poorer time tradeoff.However, one trap that debaters sometimes fall into is taking this too far, and filling the NC with a bunch of bad, blippy arguments that aren’t viable options for the 2NR. While on face this might seem strategic in terms of time tradeoffs, if the 1AR can spend very little time on a position that they know the 2NR realistically can’t/won’t go for and can just dare you to go for, it hasn’t helped you. A good rule of thumb for deciding whether to include a position in the NC should be that if you think it could be something you can give a 2NR on absent 1AR mistakes, then it can be included; otherwise, use that time with something else.In a similar vein, sometimes the best move is few, if any layers. One overlooked strategy is going one off and dumping a ton of arguments on the case – one possible iteration of this is reading a Phil NC and making a ton of framework arguments. Another possible strategy is conceding the framework and turning the Aff for the entire NC. As mentioned above, none of these strategies are “better” or “worse” – it depends on the round, opponent, and the AFF. If the framework is poorly justified, going for a framework-heavy strategy might make more sense than putting other sub-optimal arguments in the NC that don’t challenge the weakest part of the AC. And, “straight-turning” the AC for 7 minutes of the NC is a great way to catch the 1AR off guard, especially if they haven’t rigorously justified the advantages/you think your evidence is just far better.

2. Dump lots of offense on the case

Case debate is a lost art, which is unfortunate given how important it is. From being able to straight turn an advantage and collapse to that as a 2NR, to reducing the risk of the AFF to zero and going for a DA, being good at case debate is often enough to win a debate.The first important thing to keep in mind is that a good analytic is better than a bad card any day. Most AFFs and internal links aren’t rigorously justified, and evidence quality is often abysmal. If you think about arguments through the lens of “what would someone in the real world think of this?” you’ll be surprised at how weak many arguments seem outside of the bubble that’s debate.Another good lens to view arguments through whether the Aff is necessary AND sufficient; if it’s not necessary, it’s likely that the status quo solves it, and if it’s not sufficient, then a slew of alt causes likely exist. Very very few Aff arguments can hit the sweet spot of demonstrating that nothing is happening to address it now and that the Aff is the sole solution, plus that nothing else would get in the way.In line with the above, reading a combination of offense and defense can pressure the 1AR, and often force them into contradictions that make other arguments stronger. For example, if the AFF reads a warming advantage and the neg says that warming isn’t existential, and that it’s too late to address warming, many Aff answers to it being existential will hinge on a tipping point being reached that we’re dangerously close to; the 2NR can concede this argument, which lowers the bar for the other argument about it being too late if there’s such a short timeframe to act.Finally, don’t be afraid to commit to going for offense on the case. If you’re just positive that the Aff is wrong about everything, why not just read 4 minutes of turns, and not read defense that the Aff could concede to get out of the turns? Many 1ARs, due to pressure to not undercover off case positions, just blow through the case and undercover important arguments that can be a standalone 2NR.But even if case debate isn’t your thing, or you’d rather go for something else in a particular 2NR, always make sure to cover your bases on the case anyways; far too many 2NRs get there with too little time, and undercover either solid 1AR impact calculus or reasons why the case turns whatever offense the neg is going for, which allows for an easy 2AR collapse

3. Answering new AFFs

Many debaters instinctually will flip Aff if their opponent tells them at the flip that they’re breaking new; while certainly defensible, the neg still has plenty of advantages even if the Aff is new, and I’ll make the case that in most situations, being neg is ultimately still preferable. The neg still has a devastating time advantage, the ability to uplayer and moot the Aff, and most judges will show the neg a lot more love in terms of neg flex/theory due to the unpredictable nature of debating a new Aff – I’ll go into each of these below.The first, and often most essential part of debating new Affs is the prep that goes into them ahead of time. Well in advance of the tournament, you should have thought through what kind of positions you think are likely to apply and be a good “functional limit”. If philosophy is your thing, plan on going for a FW NC that you think is likely to apply to most Affs. Generic policy strats like the States CP + the Politics DA or a Process CP are likely to apply to the vast majority of affirmatives. A generic K like neoliberalism is also a strong candidate, if that’s something you feel comfortable with. The bottom line is that while not as preferable as a case-specific strategy, going for something you’re comfortable with can be effective in making the round come down to your strengths.In line with the above, one thing that all of those have in common is that they deflate the the Aff; what I mean by that is they’re all preclusive arguments and appeal to something that doesn’t rely on knowing the nuances of the Aff, or figuring out what the “trick” of the Aff is. Having several options available after the NC is helpful; for example, a solid strategy could be a T violation, the states CP, a politics DA, and a FW NC, since that opens up at least 3 independent 2NRs that would all be preclusive and not rely on winning the case debate.Finally, one thing that debaters should take advantage of (and be able to justify) is new Affs justifying more neg flexibility. Just consider how much prep goes into writing and researching a position; the Aff will know a lot more about a genuinely new position than the neg can possibly ascertain in CX and 4 minutes of prep. If the neg needs to have more options available in the NC, and the “trick” of the Aff doesn’t become clear until the 1AR, it seems incredibly reasonable for the neg to get to read an otherwise objectionable counterplan, have more leeway with conditionality, or more, because of the in-built advantage the Aff walks in with in terms of knowing substantially more about the Aff.

4. Know when to avoid (and bait) 1AR theory

It’s no secret that a lot of debaters like to restart in the 1AR by reading theory, and setting up a potential 2AR collapse to it. However, introducing new theory is always a risk issue. As my high school coach Mr. Hertzig memorably told me as a freshman, “Introducing theory is tossing a loaded gun into the fight, and you never know who will end up with it”. For the 1AR to have a theory argument that could viably be the 2AR, it probably requires 45 seconds to a minute, which seriously complicates the ability to cover the rest of the flow, especially if the neg strategically layered and put out a lot.If you’re debating someone who you know likes to go for theory, is weak at substance, and will go for it no matter what, don’t make their job easier. If you read a DA and case turns, (or even several DAs) the number of plausible 1AR theory interps they could read really should fall to 0, and in front of all but the most theory friendly judges the 2NR on theory should be a crush.Similarly, if you’re in front of someone who’s very weak at theory and is unlikely to read it, there’s no shame in taking a few more liberties in terms of number or types of advocacies, among other things. Obviously though don’t bite off more than you can chew, especially in front of a judge that’s receptive to theory, or you might end up losing by having underestimated theory.

5. Adjust to your opponent, their Aff, and their weaknesses

A good neg debater should know the 1AC better than the Aff does, and be able to know what the most threatening Aff answers and strategies are and could be in a given debate. Having read the Aff articles, rehighlighting evidence that goes your way, and just generally being able to speak intelligently about the Aff not only looks good and helps with speaker points but also greatly increases your chances of finding that knockdown counterplan that all the Aff authors agree solves the Aff, or at the very least knowing what arguments are most potentially dangerous that you’ll have to deal with.It’s also helpful to debate with comparative strengths and weaknesses in mind. As mentioned earlier, try to find the weakest parts of the 1AC and spend a lot of time attacking those. This also applies to figuring out what your opponent wants the debate to come down to, and not playing to their strengths. If you’re debating a util Aff, and your opponent is terrified of a framework debate, the basic strategic move would be to go for a framework NC. However, the next level is to be able to adjust to and predict their likely response. They might overcompensate by overcovering that in the 1AR, and you should be ready to execute something else that subsequently was undercovered as a result

Conclusion:

Making the 1AR hard is fun, and the strategic thinking involved is fulfilling and valuable to work on. That being said, while keeping these tips in mind will help, watching debates and knowing your prep well are also instrumental to successfully executing these strategies. Good luck!

The Case for Novice Packets by Lawrence Zhou

Lawrence Zhou is a Lincoln-Douglas curriculum director at VBI and an assistant LD coach at The Harker School. He was the 2014 NSDA LD National Champion and currently attends the University of Oklahoma.Thank you to Marshall Thompson for his input.

Introduction

I take the following claim to be uncontroversial: “The educational value of novice debate differs from the educational value of varsity debate”. I also take it as uncontroversial that “if the educational goal of two debaters are different, then those debates should transpire differently”. Using these two assumptions as a starting point, I hope to advance an argument for a very controversial conclusion about novice debate tournaments.Near the end of the year, talented first and second-year debaters debate for a chance at a novice or JV national championship. Two such tournaments are the Western JV & Novice National Championship and the 1st & 2nd Year National Championships at Woodward Academy. Both tournaments include a novice division for debaters with a year or less of competitive debate experience, and a JV or second year division, for debaters with two or less years of experience. The Western JV and Novice National Championships was a wonderful experience and I judged some excellent novices who show promise and future potential. Some of the novice rounds I judged, which included excellent clash and presentation, were more enjoyable than the JV counterparts. These novice debaters give me reason to hope for the next generation of debate. I was especially pleased watching several novice debaters who defeated ‘circuity’ opponents through high-quality weighing and warrants while maintaining a compelling traditional style.However, the value of these tournaments is not a reason to think they cannot be improved. Rather, the very value of these tournaments gives us all the more reason to make sure these tournaments are as excellent as they can be.Having judged at the Western JV & Novice National Championship, and planning to judge at Woodward, I have been thinking on how Novice tournament could be improved. My primary suggestion: novice packets.This brief article will:

  • outline my proposal to include evidence packets,
  • present my justification for this proposal,
  • and respond to potential objections.

I hope that this article starts a conversation about how tournaments might improve the quality of novice debate.

Proposal

What do I mean by novice packets? Novice packets are collections of evidence. Novice debaters may only read evidence from this novice packet. They may not read evidence from their own personal files that are not in the novice packet. This does not preclude them from making analytic responses to arguments but does prevent them from reading carded responses to arguments that are not in the evidence packet. A novice packet could be also referred to as a uniform card file.The novice packet would not be created by the tournament. Instead, each participating school in the novice division would be able to submit evidence to the novice packet a few weeks before the tournament begins. Those schools would submit the prep that they would expect their novice debaters to read and respond to. The novice packet would then be posted some period of time before the tournament. The only guidelines for submission would be that the arguments should be able to be understood by novices.Novice debaters would then be able create cases and block files using the evidence provided in the novice packet. This would not require novices to write entirely new cases for the tournament as they can submit the evidence that they cite in their existing cases to the novice packet, although novices could certainly construct new cases before the tournament using the novice packet.This is not just disclosure for novices. There are two primary differences between this proposal and common disclosure practices. First, novices are not constrained to reading only certain cases. The core evidence packet enables novices to construct affirmative and negative cases using the same evidence as every other novice in the pool but add their own unique insight and analysis to the cases. Unlike disclosure, novices don’t have to read the exact same cases as everyone else. Second, novices are not permitted to “break new”. The core evidence packet constrains what novices can read the entire tournament as they may not read evidence outside of the packet. Unlike disclosure, novices are not permitted to read evidence or cases that are not in the evidence packet.There is a precedent for this type of proposal. Many policy tournaments have the novice division use a novice packet. One such tournament is the JW Patterson Invitational in Oklahoma which is a finals bid in policy debate. On their invite page, it describes how a novice packet would work in practice.

There will be a novice debate evidence packet that must be used at this tournament.  Novice policy debaters are encouraged to using files from the Oklahoma novice policy packet.  I will email the packet to anyone interested (just ask) and post it on this site soon.If a novice policy team wants to use an Aff case or negative arguments that are not included in the Oklahoma novice packet they MUST email Bryan Gaston (tournament director, bgaston@heritagehall.com) the full files (this includes all evidence they might read in the round) by Sept. 22nd.  The files will be distributed to all coaches in the novice division.  In the event that there is no case neg for "X" teams Aff or answers for "X" Neg argument I will allow coaches to send me additional files that answer Affs or Neg arguments until October 1st.  I will then email out the supplement files.  If I do not get an email from "X" teams coach with the non-OK packet Aff and Neg args they want to run by Sept. 22nd it will not be included in the updated novice policy packet and cannot be used.PLEASE do not abuse my flexibility on this issue by sending me files your novices will likely not read or attempt to flood the novice case list or evidence packet with a ridiculous amount of files.  I want the novice division to be a solid teaching and training ground where there is a decent set of predictable arguments while not forcing everyone out of state to use the Oklahoma packet.

I find this to be a very reasonable example of how a novice packet might work in practice at a tournament. You can download the novice packet as a zip folder from the tabroom page to see how a novice packet might look.

In Favor of My Proposal

Perhaps this sounds like a plausible proposal, but one may wonder what the benefit of a novice packet would be.

Benefit 1: this increases clash in rounds.

Right now, some novice rounds include tons of direct clash, but many rounds lack almost any clash. Sometimes novice debaters read cases neither they nor their opponents understand. This article has a particularly well-written section highlighting the problem of bad arguments in debate. The two types of bad arguments that the author identifies as problems in novice policy debate are “A. Block dumping- this is where a novice team is given a file they know nothing about and just encouraged to read blocks” and “B. Purposefully selecting obscure crap that other teams will not have learned about yet as they are in their first year of debate.” These trends are already seeping into Lincoln-Douglas debate. This occurs because coaches, particularly older varsity debaters interested in proving themselves as coaches, provide their novices with evidence, cases, or blocks that none of the novices have seen before. Alternatively, novices may have been taught about argument types like theory and kritiks, and choose to employ those types to confuse their opponent. Whether the coaches or debaters are to blame, the result is a drastic decrease in substantive engagement during the round.A novice packet would rectify this issue. By limiting novice debaters to certain core arguments, it would allow debaters to substantively engage in every debate. Novices can ensure they understand each argument being made, allowing a focus just on the arguments themselves. The possibility of obfuscation would largely be eliminated. What value is there in winning a novice round if no one gains any lasting educational benefit?Obviously, this is not something we want for varsity debaters, where this would obviously decrease innovation and disincentivize research.  These are values that are far less important for novices at the moment than the inculcation of core skills like clash and engagement. Junior varsity debaters should definitely be encouraged to innovate beyond the packet, but there’s little to no reason why novices should be doing this at the expense of in-round clash.And for those that claim that novices should be ready to debate these positions and just learn how to beat it, I’ll let Scott Phillips respond to this:

And lest you say “this is just some whine, they should learn to beat it” as if I didn’t already explain why that is possible, remember that the students reading these arguments generally HAVE NO IDEA WHAT THEY ARE TALKING ABOUT. If you really want to argue that point I have nothing else to say to you- I have seen a ton of novice debates first hand and seen the way they read blocks without knowing why or where to read them, read the same blocks regardless of what arguments the other team makes etc. It’s not a defensible position.

Benefit 2: this equalizes the playing field for younger debaters.

Right now, novice tournaments are full of debaters from relatively large programs who can afford to send novices to these tournaments for the extra practice. These novices are able to draw from relatively large varsity files on the current topic. However, smaller schools will also sometimes send novices and these novices would be immediately disadvantaged upon entering the pool, with fewer files and resources to draw from. There are rounds at these tournaments where novices from larger schools have blocks to everything their opponent says including indicts of specific studies. Novices from smaller schools who have done their own work simply can’t keep up with their opponent’s prep.A novice packet would remedy these inequalities. Larger programs would not necessarily benefit from having massive backfiles and topic prep to draw from. Instead, everyone would have access to the arguments and evidence read at the tournament, which allows novices from smaller programs to enter on a more equal playing field. A large school wouldn’t be able to win a novice round simply by loading their debaters with more prep than a novice from a smaller school. These rounds are more likely to be educational when both debaters are forced to draw from the same evidence and learn how to argue the evidence on a relatively equal playing field. This is uniquely important for novices who have yet to really solidify their research skills in such a way that would properly reward increased prep.

Benefit 3: this helps maintain the pedagogical integrity of novice debate.

Think about how any educational activity works. If you want a student to learn calculus, you don’t teach them all the math they need to know in their first year. Instead, you teach them in stages which slowly increase in complexity. Encouraging a student to try and learn all the principles of mathematics at once, will result in the students not learning any of them as well. Debate is no different. If you want students to learn core skills, such as flowing, argument generation, weighing, and crystallization, then you want to allow them to debate in a context where they can focus on those skills, rather than focus on trying to comprehend arguments they are not yet trained to understand.However, the immediate goal of coaches and students is to try and win, not try to learn. Debaters choose strategies that they think will help them win, not that will maximize their long-term education. Perhaps this is lamentable, but it is a clear reality we need to consider. And given this reality we should take positive steps to structure tournaments to encourage sound pedagogical practices, so that coaches are not forced to choose between their students learning and their students winning.Perhaps some have considered banning progressive arguments in the novice division. There is perhaps some value in considering this idea, but this doesn’t really get to the core of the issue I have with current novice debates. It’s not necessarily that they read progressive arguments, but that they read positions that they clearly don’t comprehend in a manner that’s anti-educational and try to spring new positions on other novice debaters to confuse rather than engage them. I have no qualms with a counterplan being read, I just have qualms with surprise counterplans that novices can’t engage. This is something that only a novice packet can deal with.Additionally, this proposal seems far less enforceable than a novice packet. A judge can quickly determine with a control-f whether or not a piece of evidence was in the packet. Determining what counts as a kritik or a counterplan or an alternative becomes rather tricky. It also isn’t particularly easy to enforce because many judges in the novice division are varsity debaters who either don’t care enough to enforce such a rule or proactively encourage novice debaters to read progressive arguments. Finally, it’s unenforceable because novice debaters will just disguise these arguments as NCs or responses on case. In the end, a novice packet seems more enforceable and is better at encouraging education.

Responding to Objections

Certainly, this idea has its drawbacks and I aim to address some of these potential concerns here.

Objection 1: this discourages novices from cutting their own evidence.

One of the most important things that novices can learn is research skills. The ability to find, read and process high-quality academic research on both sides of an issue is an incredibly valuable skill. Learning research skills also incentivizes novices to stay in the activity. It’s part of what hooks novices into the activity as they discover new subjects of interest. There is real worry that novice packets would disincentive novice research.The first thing to realize is that it’s happening now. Big schools with large varsity programs are already producing evidence for their novices to read in novice rounds. These novices are already not reading their own evidence in rounds and are merely reading what the coaches or varsity debaters of these larger teams are telling them to read. This isn’t speculation but empirically confirmed. Many novices are entering rounds trying to read disads, counterplans, and kritiks they barely understand because they haven’t cut them. Minimally, there is almost no chance this proposal discourages novices from cutting their own evidence any more than the status quo does. Even debaters without resources will likely still continue to produce evidence in general since the disincentive remains relatively small and the benefit of increasing resource equity seems to outweigh.Second, this proposal most likely will incentivize novice debaters to cut more of their own evidence for the novice packet. When the value of stolen varsity prep becomes significantly lowered, novice debaters can no longer rely on the larger files of the varsity debaters to carry them through the tournament, especially when lots of varsity prep like advanced disads and kritiks won’t fly in the novice division. This forces novice debaters to return back to the core issues in the topic and will likely incentivize novice debaters to cut evidence directly related to the central issues of the topic that they can submit to the novice packet. Given a lot of varsity debaters or coaches won’t be heavily incentivized to cut tons of new cards for the novice division and the novice packet, novice debaters will likely have to cut at least some of their new prep for the packet which only benefits those novices. It also won’t result in novices not cutting their own evidence because ultimately, novices will write their own cases using evidence in the packet.Finally, even if this does slightly discourage novices from cutting their own evidence, that’s mostly an issue for the schools sending their novices who should be requiring their novice students to do at least a significant amount of the novice prep they submit for the evidence packet. Ultimately, it’s a coaching practice that tournaments don’t really have any control over one way or another, and the benefit of increasing clash in rounds should trump any small risk that coaches won’t force their kids to cut cards.

Objection 2: this discourages novices from thinking on their feet.

If novice debaters only have to read evidence from the packet, then you can functionally script every novice speech in a way that really prevents novices from thinking on their feet. This objection alleges that such a packet decreases in round creativity.As with the previous objection, this is something is already happening. It should be obvious in the case where novices are reading varsity arguments they clearly don’t understand that they aren’t really thinking on their feet, they are really just reading the frontlines in the file or repeating taglines from the cards without understanding anything about them. This is hardly ideal debate.Second, this isn’t unique to a novice packet. All novices will have some blocks and prep to draw from and so regardless of the existence of a novice packet, novices will end up reading prep and not thinking on their feet as much as we would like.Third, I think a novice packet would actually increase thinking on the spot. The better debater has to distinguish themselves from every other novice debater by correctly reacting and interacting with arguments. Merely reading the blocks and evidence from the evidence packet that everyone has access to will not be sufficient. Recall that the evidence packet doesn’t stop debaters from coming with analytic responses both before and during the round. This is where thinking on the spot and hard work are still rewarded. Good analytic responses in round that are directly responsive and comparative to what was said in round actually increases thinking on the spot relative to a world where novice debaters rely on their “special varsity” blocks and aren’t incentivized to come up with in round responses to distinguish themselves as the better debater. Novice debaters are also rewarded for making smart choices about card selection. Since not all evidence is created, this forces novice debaters to parse through the evidence packet and select the best evidence for the situation.

Objection 3: this punishes novices who have learned advanced argumentation and rewards novices for not learning more about debate.

If novice debaters can’t read a lot of different arguments or types of arguments, then it seems to unnecessarily punish novices who have put in the extra effort to learn more about the topic or advanced argument types like theory or kritiks. We wouldn’t punish a TOC-qualled debater for reading a kritik that their opponent doesn’t understand at a bid tournament, so why should we punish these novices?First, if a novice really wants to practice their newfound skills or demonstrate their mastery of advanced argumentation, there’s nothing stopping them from entering JV at these tournaments where these practices are allowed. Novice debaters who are truly advanced enough to competently read and defend advanced arguments probably shouldn’t be in the novice division anyways. Maybe they want to win a novice tournament, but that is hardly a reason to deny so many other novices an educational round.The second problem with this objection is it doesn’t take seriously the differences between varsity and novice. Even though both varsity and novice debaters are focused on winning, there is a difference between what varsity and novice debaters should be learning. These novice debates shouldn’t be focused on rewarding debaters for learning a kritik, but for cementing core debate skills like learning how to engage arguments substantively and directly.Third, this doesn’t encourage novices to not learn more about debate. Should novices need a forum to learn about advanced arguments in round, many other opportunities to encounter a disad or kritik will present itself to those novices when they enter JV or varsity. There’s no reason why novices need to encounter these arguments as novices when they’re still trying to develop core skills. It’s similar to when overzealous varsity debaters try to teach their novices about advanced theory concepts when their novices are still having trouble understanding the difference between offense and defense. Those varsity debaters will defend their actions by claiming “they’ll encounter these arguments soon, better expose them to it now.” However, this practice clearly just hurts these novices in the long run who fail to solidify core debate skills. There’s a reason why you start with learning speech times before you learn about RVIs.Finally, the ultimate impact of the objection is just that judges would not be truly rewarding who did the better debating because you’re failing to reward debaters who have mastered advanced arguments. However, I think that a novice packet actually does a better job of rewarding who did the better debating. If both sides have access to the same arguments and the same evidence, the better debater is the one who can win by demonstrating stronger core debate skills like weighing and warranting. Ultimately, in the novice division especially, this seems like a much stronger test of who does the actual better debating.

Conclusion

A world where novices are just taught to write their own stock cases and coaches encourage novice debaters to focus on fundamental debate skills like clash would likely be preferable. I personally would prefer such a world. However, given the competitive incentives at a debate tournament, it leads debaters and coaches to engage in practices that maximize the short-term potential for winning at the expense of the long-term benefit of long-term education.Ultimately, I think that novice debate tournaments, especially these larger “novice championships”, could be significantly benefited from the introduction of a novice packet. This isn’t a totally new proposal given its roots in novice policy debate. But I think it’s a proposal that should be taken seriously by novice tournaments to truly help improve novice debate. 

#DebateToo: A Plea for Integrity by Nina Potischman

Nina Potischman debated for Hunter College High School for four years, and is currently a freshman at Pomona College. Her senior year she was top seed, top speaker, and a finalist at the TOC, and won a number of national tournaments.Thank you to Maddy Stevens, SunHee Simon, and Marshall Thompson for their input. My first year at camp, I was told one of the counselors had made a female student drill with him while he showered, so I should avoid going to his office hours alone. At the time I wondered, if young girls had to be warned about this person, why was he allowed to teach at camp? Since first joining LD debate, I knew that there were people that I never want to be alone with: some were camp counselors, others were upperclassman, while others were judges and coaches.Throughout my time in debate, I realized that many of my own experiences fit with widespread collective knowledge of who constituted a threat. Most interactions that made me uncomfortable were not isolated, but rather formed a tapestry of shared experiences throughout the community.The #MeToo movement has shaped my thoughts about how systems, despite collective awareness of wrongdoing, sustain support for prominent individuals. It has given a platform to victims of sexual assault, and has pushed people to take their experiences seriously and ensure that abusers do not retain power within the industry. The movement has given visibility to problems many were already aware of, and has emphasized the importance of speaking out against sexual violence.As Time’s Up and #MeToo gained traction, individuals in debate discussed their own experiences with sexual harassment and violence in debate.[1] There are people involved in debate who have harassed members of the community and exploited age differences and power imbalances. There are people who have made girls afraid to attend tournaments, made them feel unwelcome in the activity, and objectified successful female debaters. Many girls have voiced concern about these individuals to camp directors and school coaches with no avail.So why are these people still at debate tournaments? Why are they still coaching? Why are they hired by camps? Do those who hire coaches and judges not care enough to find out about the integrity of those they entrust to supervise young students, or do they know and not take these issues seriously?Debate is no different from the rest of the world; it is not free from sexual violence. We often forget that debaters are children, and that many people in positions of power have just graduated from high school. Many are given too much power over younger students, and it should not surprise us that our current system allows this abuse. There are significant issues with hiring practices in debate that shield people from accountability: harassment and exploitation are systemic problems, not isolated occurrences.Many who came forward in response to #MeToo about their experiences with sexual violence did not name their perpetrators. Some, justifiably, fear that giving names could cause school administrations to shut down their team.[2] Others have spoken out against specific individuals in the past and have seen nothing change; there is still a cloud of privilege and prestige shielding powerful members of debate from criticism and repercussions for their actions. We can not expect children to take on complete responsibility for ensuring perpetrators are not rehired. We must change social norms in debate that allow threatening people to gain power.Part of the problem is a bizarre hiring practice for debate camps and teams. If someone is a successful debater, they will receive offers for coaching students and working at debate camps, without even applying for jobs or submitting information for a background check. The interests at hand are clear: if you were good at debate, you’ll get a job.But leadership requires integrity. It should be a bare minimum that debate instructors never pose a threat to adolescents. Camps require positive evidence of the ability to teach debate, but with students’ safety, they presume that instructors can be trusted. We don’t merely hope our instructors understand debate, so why are we satisfied to merely hoping that our instructors will not abuse their power?There has been some effort to take these issues seriously. Recently, VBI held a survey at the end of camp that asked students if there were people they felt should not be instructors (one of the people I listed was not hired the next year). However, camps, including VBI, and teams that are making an effort can and must do more. There are a number of things that can be done to proactively combat sexual assault and harassment (these suggestions are a starting point, and by no means an exhaustive list):

  • Coaches should actively reach out to other members of the community to find out who should not have authority. There are a number of instances in which sexual harassment has been reported to some coaches, but others are unaware of the incident.[3]
  • Take seriously the claims of those who accuse others of sexual harassment – investigate these accusations, and respect the wishes of survivors when determining how to handle the situation.[4]
  • Put women and people of color who are more aware of issues regarding discrimination and harassment within debate in positions of power.[5]

To debate camps and coaches: it is not a defense to say that you “didn’t know.” You are obligated to make sure that people you hire will not pose a danger to children; the burden is not on others to do that work for you. You owe it to your students and you owe it to your peers to care more about the safety of your students than about the competitive success of your instructors.The burden must no longer fall on female debaters to know who is a threat. Men in debate must take responsibility and action to prevent sexual harassment in debate. You cannot continue to turn to each other and ask why women and people of color do not populate your space when you refuse to prioritize their safety over the ego of an abuser whose only redemption is the number of words per minute he can speak.[6]


[1] Thank you to Maddy Stevens for this contribution.[2] Thank you to Maddy Stevens for this contribution.[3] One camp consults a team of first year out women who they are consulting about all potential hires before finalizing offers to work at camp. I like this idea because often people who are farther out of the activity are not aware of younger debaters that may pose a threat to students.[4] Thank you to SunHee Simon for this contribution.[5] There are additional steps that should be taken to prevent sexual harassment. Because discussing them at length would potentially distract from the central issue of the article, I have included them here:
  • As a coach with a student who has been accused of harassment, it is your responsibility to inform others that this person should not be hired.
  • Run rigorous background checks on all staff members. Hiring camps and teams should contact references and confirm the eligibility of staff for hire or rehire.
  • Monitor staff and ensure that they are not alone in private spaces with students. Some camps have had students work alone in instructor’s rooms, which should not be allowed.
  • Reach out to administrators at other camps to ensure that you do not hire someone that was fired from a different camp for sexual harassment.
  • Camps that fire someone for harassment must also inform others that this person should not be hired.
  • Camps should create forums where people can easily submit concerns about staff members.

[6] Thank you to Maddy Stevens for this contribution.

Upward Trajectory: How to Improve Quickly by Raffi Piliero

Raffi Piliero debated for Harrison High School for 4 years, clearing at the TOC twice, and finishing as bid leader his senior year. He also won several national tournaments and several top speaker awards, and now debates for Georgetown University. 

Introduction:

Nobody is perfect. There will never be a 1AR that makes 0 mistakes, an NR that executes everything exactly as the judge would have hoped, or a debater that wins every single debate in a total blowout. Whether someone is a novice who’s never listened to a debate before, let alone given a speech, or someone vying to win the TOC, everyone can stand to improve, and continue to maintain skills over time.This article is simple; it outlines what you should do to improve, regardless of who you are or your experience. I’ll start by offering some general tips, and then talking more specifically about things to do based on beginner, intermediate, or advanced skill levels.

General tips:

A. There’s no offseason:

For a lot of debaters, when their last tournament ends in the spring, they figure they can put away their Tabletote and flow pens for another few months until camp rolls around, and forget about debate for a while. While certainly it’s important not to burn out (and I’d even suggest giving yourself a week to rest and come back rejuvenated), the months in between the season ending and camp are ideal times to improve, not regressing and coming to camp worse than you were at the end of the season. Camp is a time to learn from instructors you won’t see during the year, and to build skills you otherwise wouldn’t have the chance to; ideally time isn’t spent re-learning how to spread and fixing word economy that vanished in the months you took off.The best debaters recognize that the time between the season ending and beginning again is an incredible opportunity, since qualitatively different skills can be emphasized and improved than during the season. Most debaters, during the season, are preoccupied with scouting positions on the NDCA Wiki, writing new AFFs, frontlining, and thinking about the topic; these things are important, and necessary for success, but are things that one need not worry about during the offseason. Instead, once the season is over, there’s a golden opportunity. I personally would use the time to read books about debate, whether critical literature, philosophy, or just debate theory articles to learn more about the mechanics of arguments. Other people I know would watch tapes of their debates from the previous season to figure out some tics or common mistakes they were making continuously. These are all important, but are things that take time and trade off with topical prep that yields more instant, immediate returns; in the off season, there’s no such tradeoff, and these help improve skills that make the difference during the season.Although certainly a shorter period of time, breaks from school also present a great opportunity for this type of skills building. Although obviously there’s a topic out that needs to be prepped (and that should be the first priority) given the amount of free time, doing any of the above can only help

B. Work at it daily

Wanting to improve is a great (and necessary) first step. But what really counts is actually doing it. Working daily on speaking drills, speeches, prep, or whatever you’ve decided to do is important to continue to improve. The more you work, the more you will improve. Sloppily doing work a couple of times a week with Facebook or TV in the background won’t help nearly as much as committing to actually improving.In line with this, writing out manageable goals and setting schedules for yourself can help you stay organized. For example, if you write out that you want to get to quarterfinals of your tournament in a month, and will cut 10 cards a day and do 20 minutes of speaking drills, you’re setting much more attainable and precise goals than just generically “hoping to improve and do well”. You also then can know if you’re doing what you need to, or if you’re falling short

Beginners:

For people with no debate experience, breaking into it seems daunting. Everyone seems like they’re speaking incomprehensibly fast, making arguments that are convoluted and confusing, and just not debating at all like the presidential debates you’d see on TV. However, everyone starts there inevitably, and there are things that can be done to improve

A. Watch rounds online.

The most overwhelming thing for most people starting out is the speed people speak at. The solution is to start training the ear to understand it. Watching videos of rounds online that are slightly slower than average circuit speed is a good start; building up to average and then fast circuit speeds is something that takes time, but eventually can happen. Additionally, watching college policy debates can be useful; they’re quite fast but usually very clear as well, and are a good test for if your ear is getting attuned to high speeds

B. Learn from others

One of the biggest factors for me sticking with debate and improving was the amazing support I had from varsity teammates and my coach who taught me a lot of the basics of circuit debate. However, many people lack this type of base; instead, one helpful thing is to reach out to others in the community (or at a camp) and ask questions.There’s no need to be nervous; nobody is going to judge you for being inexperienced and wanting to learn, because everyone was there at some point. Reaching out to others and asking about what an argument means, how a particular strategy is executed, or even their thoughts on the topic can help you understand how successful circuit debaters or coaches think, which can only help you learn more.

C. Debate

This sounds obvious, but people really don’t utilize this enough. If you feel unprepared about executing in rounds, then do it more. Go to local tournaments with low pressure, low stake environments; regardless of the final results, you’ll get more experience and more rounds in, and can get input from judges. If tournaments don’t seem available, doing practice rounds with teammates or even just friendly figures in the community can help create the aforementioned benefits of rounds

Intermediate:

The people who fall into this group are those who have debated for a little bit, know the basics, but want to start achieving more prolonged levels of circuit success. These debaters might go even at tournaments, or go 4-2 and miss clearing on speaks; there are several tweaks that make the difference between someone that barely misses elims and someone who gets to the bid round, or bids

A. Give speeches, and do speaking drills

This is something else that should be second-nature, but a lot of people don’t do. The difference between a decent circuit debater and a great one often just comes down to technical proficiency. Being able to speak quickly, clearly, and efficiently comes down to practicing it a ton.While I’d argue that being able to speak extremely quickly isn’t even essential (or optimal for debaters where it trades off with clarity or efficiency), being efficient is the replacement for that. If a time-crunched 1AR wastes 40 seconds (or more) on inefficient phrasings, repetition, and other inefficiencies, they likely lose to an equal debater just given structural constraints of the time-crunched 1AR. Or, if the NR says the right arguments, but they were so unclearly delivered that the judge didn’t understand them, that debater probably loses to an ethos-y and well-framed 2AR that explains arguments in a coherent way.The solution is putting in the time and giving speeches and speaking drills. I won’t go into a lot of the specific drills that can be done (Danny DeBois wrote a fantastic article a few years back outlining most of the ones that I would recommend; I attached the link at the end of the article), but drills themselves are important. At minimum, doing speaking drills on a daily basis to build speed and clarity is important to form the muscle memory in the mouth that lets one just speak naturally and fluently without thinking about it, making it more habitual. Giving speeches and redoes can help one hone the speech and make it stronger, so that it can be executed better in real time

B. Watch the best

If you want to learn how to be the best, and to take the next step, you need to know what you’re aiming for. Whether it’s watching the best debaters of your year or some of the most successful from previous years, watching top people can help teach important skills. The way I’d recommend watching rounds is to pause after each speech, and think about what your strategy would be, what you predict they would do, and to think backwards from what their final speech and overall strategy should be. That way, you’re actively making decisions in a high level round, so that when you find yourself in those situations, you know how to handle it and to think proactively about in-round strategy

C. Know your prep

One big issue that prevents a lot of solid, but not great debaters from taking the next step forward is not cutting their own evidence, whether just because they’re handed it by teammates or coaches, or because they just use the evidence that other people have cut and just recut it off of the wiki. You’ll never know an argument well enough just by giving it a cursory read-through on the bus ride to a tournament, especially compared to someone who not only read that article, but read the 3 articles that the author footnotes and is responding to. Being able to talk intelligently about a card isn’t just useful for speaker points and CX; it helps you know what arguments interact with each other, and helps you make the most intuitive answers to various substantive. positions

Advanced:

Improvement for top tier debaters is one of the more underrated types of improvement, because people don’t realize how important it is. At the beginner and intermediate levels, debates are often won just by mistakes that one person makes, and aren’t often as close. However, in advanced debates, rounds are usually won between two quite proficient debaters who capitalize on mistakes, and win by out-debating the other. The difference between winning a tournament and losing in octas to a talented debater might be a single piece of evidence you cut and highlighted at 11PM, or the extra analytic you were able to put out on theory because of that extra 10 seconds of efficiency you saved; rounds are won at the margins, and come down to small things

A. Don’t forget the basics

Just because you have 5 bids doesn’t mean that the 1AR should have inefficiencies, that the 2AR shouldn’t tell a story, or that the NC can be read incomprehensibly. These things matter, and are often forgotten about at the higher levels of debate. These all require practice, so a lot of the drills outlined earlier in the article should still be done

B. Innovate

The first thing that many people notice on the circuit is how often a lot of the same cards get used and recycled; those cards came from somewhere. This is true both of generic framework and K cards, and of topic specific positions. While it’s OK to model a position someone else has run in a pinch, ideally you’re the one who has the prep that people are modeling. Do tons of research, and find the articles buried in the literature that aren’t on the first 2 pages of a Google search. Be the one who people are recutting from the NDCA wiki, not the one doing most of the mining. That way, when TOC rolls around and people are still reading the cards from the AFF you cobbled together in January, you have brand new prep and positions that nobody knew was coming.Honestly, this is probably what singularly distinguishes the advanced, good debaters from the truly great ones. Being able to make new arguments, have recent evidence, and stay on top of the ball means that everyone else is forced to be reactive while you’re proactively changing the game.

C. Attack your weaknesses

It’s important to be self-reflexive; despite how many tournaments you’ve bid at or won, you aren’t perfect. There will always be someone in the country who has a comparative strength over you and that you wouldn’t want to debate on a particular skillset. Once you’ve identified areas you’re weak in, and concerned about, it’s time to try and fix it. Doing practice rounds with people on concern areas, or just giving speeches can help. For example, an excellent util debater doesn’t need to be as good on philosophy as they are on their main strength, but they shouldn’t be in a spot where they’re sweating bullets if they’re Aff against a good phil debater.Being able to also make the round come down to what you’re good at is another important way to shift away from weaknesses. Following the above example of the util debater who is weak at philosophy, they should pref low judges who will be receptive to dense philosophy, or get good at winning util tricks (or even theory hedges like epistemic modesty and theoretically justified frameworks) to make the framework debate avoidable.

D. Attack your opponents’ weaknesses

As mentioned above, nobody is perfect. Mistakes people make often aren’t isolated, and among top debaters, positive reinforcement like wins breed complacency where people don’t try to fix mistakes and continue making them.Watching rounds of your main competition, whether at tournaments or online, can help you to figure out what those weaknesses are. This type of scouting can help you know which types of judges you want to pref, which types of arguments you want to make, and foreshadow what strategies you think they’ll do against you.For example, my senior year, I was worried about a particular AFF; I watched a number of debates where teams read this position, and I timed the amount of time they spent answering Topicality in the 1AR. I then decided that I would read a super short T argument whenever debating it just to get a positive time tradeoff, since it would be shorter than the prewritten frontlines that were continuously read against it. This type of scouting helped me think ahead to the end of the debate, and what I thought my best arguments and options would be based on the predictability of some opponents’ responses to arguments.

Conclusion:

Improvement isn’t something that only happens at a particular point in time, or for a particular skillset, but something continuous. I hope this article was helpful in giving some general tips and guidelines; obviously, every person is different and learns differently, but a lot of the general ideas hopefully can help you figure out weaknesses and hone strengths.Referenceshttps://www.vbriefly.com//2014/11/26/drillin-like-a-villain-how-to-get-better-at-debate-by-danny-debois/

A Lost Art: The Issue Summary Speech in PF Debate By Abe Fraifeld

The average summary speech is not a summary; it is a brazen attempt to cover 18-20 minutes of content in two minutes while adding extra analysis. Under the average PF judge’s current expectations, the first summary speech is the hardest to deliver in all of debate. In fact, as I’ve written elsewhere, the natural limit on speed in PF means first speakers meeting expectations on the flow have to cut corners. They can either choose to fulfill flow-related responsibilities, or they can speak eloquently and remain academically honest. This dilemma is illustrated by some basic math: Let’s say a PF round consists of five main contention level arguments (two on the Pro, three on the Con), and each one has been taken out in two ways. Judges expect the Pro first speaker to

  • Extend defensive arguments against each Con argument. [3]
  • Answer responses to their arguments. [4]
  • Extend their arguments [2]
  • Weigh [1]

3a + 4b + 2c + d = 120.Let’s say it takes 30 seconds to weigh arguments and close a speech. That leaves 90 seconds, which means the first speaker has an average of 10 seconds per task per argument.Developing a PF argument can take longer than the time allotted to the whole summary speech. Summaries reduce arguments to sound-bytes, causing them to lose their nuance and sometimes their persuasive power.On the other hand, simplifying arguments often means stripping evidence of its original intent. A time-efficiency-driven trend I find disturbing: summary speakers boost the power of their evidence by claiming the resolution is the independent variable in the cause-effect relationship the evidence identifies. “The probability of war increases by 147% when moving from an adolescent stage rivalry without an arms race to one with an arms race; a similar change from a mature rivalry without an arms race to one with an arms race increases the probability of war by 331%.” In the summary becomes “Anti-missile systems increase the probability of war by three times.” Another - asserting causal relationships when the evidence does not. “States that passed Universal Background Checks have lower rates of gun violence” becomes “UBCs save thousands of lives.” It is possible that the arguments that justify these claims may have been made earlier in the round, but dropping the nuanced argument in favor of the repackaged, super-charged argument is dishonest and bad for debate.Summary speakers don’t want to be dishonest; they are just extremely rushed. Changing the time limits is an option, but in the meantime, I propose that we rethink the standards for the summary speech. In a truly public forum, debaters would be rewarded for marrying storytelling with technical arguments. They’d be rewarded for recombining arguments in ways that make sense instead of truncating them. This is what PF debaters used to do. Before the summary speech was just a rebuttal speech with more responsibilities, it was a true summary that, even at the highest levels of debate, began with the words “This round boils down to two (or three) main issues.” I am not nostalgic for 2007 PF. I think the event is much more research-oriented and argumentatively creative than it was. But I am nostalgic for some of the conventions. I’m curious if an issue-summary would work in a modern PF round. It would take a case optimized for the strategy, significant pre-round planning, and a grouping-guru as a first speaker. The teams that pulls it off will dramatically improve their lay appeal. The teams that master it will make the summary speech much easier and more efficient. And if judges start to prefer this type of speech, the event will become much more accessible and respectable.How to give an “Issue Summary”An issue summary is one that puts arguments into two to three broad categories instead of going in flow order. It synthesizes the round rather than reviewing it. I cannot give a precise template for the speech, but I can provide some important principles to live by.

  1. Stop caring about the order of the flow. There are a few reasons a reordered late-round speech may be better. First, teams deliberately design cases to cover different aspects of the topic in each contention. This means that going in order kills the narrative of the summary speech. Second, opposite sides almost always impact very similarly. For example, on the South Korea topic, most teams discussed China and North Korea on both sides. An AFF-NEG summary speech would go China, North Korea China, North Korea, where an issue summary would deal with all arguments about China’s reaction to anti-missile systems first, and North Korea’s second. Debaters miss out on opportunities to highlight clash if they go strictly line by line, which is a problem because judges often get confused about argument interaction when clash isn’t explicitly identified. Even experienced judges get frustrated when the clash isn’t resolved in one cohesive block of the speech, though they often misdiagnose the strategic misstep as a lack of weighing. Third, debaters who go in order repeat themselves a whole lot. I write “double covered the argument about x” on an enormous percentage of my ballots. Essentially, flow-style summary speakers have a tendency to repeat arguments everywhere they apply on the flow. A classic example: the summary speaker extends an overview, extends their case, and then re-applies the overview to their opponent’s case when they reach it. This is an inefficient use of time.

  2. Do your best to ensure the issues unambiguously divide the arguments made in the round. You don’t want to categorize arguments in ways that are easy to misconstrue or confuse the judge. Your best bet is to pre-determine category options before you walk into the round and try to fit the arguments into your categories as best you can.

  3. Weigh between the issues. Argument-to-argument weighing is dangerous because it either leaves out arguments or becomes so time consuming that the quality of the rest of the speech suffers. Issue-to-issue weighing is much more time-efficient, it is often much more intuitive, and the judge will appreciate that your weighing encapsulates the whole round.

I hope this article inspires some to try out the strategy. Here is a video of Harker JJ using the strategy in 2010.Abraham Fraifeld the former VBI Director of Public Forum Debate. Over the past four years, he has coached Trinity Prep and Walt Whitman’s Public Forum teams. Abraham’s students won Yale, the New York City Round Robin, the New York City Invitational, Glenbrooks, the Florida Novice State tournament, and closed out the Tournament of Champions. In 2016, Abraham’s students were in semi-finals of the NDCA National Tournament, finished 7th at the NSDA National Tournament, and reached quarterfinals or later at Grapevine, Yale, Blue Key, and Minneapple. In high school, Abraham reached six final rounds and accumulated twelve bids to the Tournament of Champions.